Species of Syllogism 273
which suggest that an argument may be both predicative and hypothetical;
and the Introduction to Logic will give its readers a strong contrary impression.
All of that is quite true. Nonetheless, it is reasonable to conclude from the
wisps of evidence that at least one ancient logician was at least sometimes
aware that every argument is not, so to speak, confined to a single syllogistic
form: an argument may, in principle, have two—or more—distinct and
non-subordinate valid forms.
In that case, syllogisms cannot be arranged under species and genera. You
may talk of kinds or sorts of arguments. You may not talk of species of
arguments—unless, of course, you use the word ‘species’ in a relaxed sense.
If logicians occasionally talk about kinds or sorts or even species of
arguments, they also—and perhaps more often—talk about forms of argu-
ment. Now the forms of argument in which a logician is interested can be
arranged into a genuine Porphyrean tree, from which we may pick—for
example—the sequence: syllogism, predicative syllogism, first figure syllo-
gism, Barbara. That is not the same sequence as before, though it is expressed
in the same words. For in it Barbara is no longer an infima species:itis
an individual—an individual syllogistic form. No such individual belongs
to more than one lowest species, and the classificatory scheme is saved. As
for arguments and syllogisms—concrete, individual arguments and concrete,
individual syllogisms—they are not forms, and so they do not appear on the
tree at all. Rather, they have or possess or show forms. And an item may have
a plurality of forms without thereby prejudicing the Porphyrean structure of
the tree of forms.
If you want to talk seriously about species of syllogism, then, you had better
be thinking of species of syllogistic forms, not of species of concrete syllogisms.
Strictly speaking, a syllogism—according to the ancient definitions—is an
argument: it has premisses which are either true or false, and a conclusion
which either follows or fails to follow from the premisses. Barbara is not a
syllogism: Barbara has no premisses and no conclusion—rather, instances or
cases of Barbara have premisses and conclusions. Barbara is a syllogistic mood
or a syllogistic form. That is perfectly clear, and it was perfectly clear to the old
logicians. Nonetheless, the old logicians, Galen among them, will frequently
talk of, say, ‘the first syllogism in the first figure’ and thereby designate the
syllogistic form Barbara; and in general, they use the word ‘syllogism’ often
enough to refer to syllogistic forms and not to concrete arguments. Indeed,
I suspect that their most common use of the word ‘syllogism’ fails to accord
with their formal definition of the word ‘syllogism’. That will vex pedants;