A Principle of Bivalence 5
such-and-such. The modern Principle of Bivalence says nothing about
assertion. How significant a difference that is depends in part on how the
term ‘proposition’ is to be understood. For example, if a proposition is
anything which may be proposed or put forward for consideration, and if
something can be proposed if and only if it can be asserted, then something
will be a proposition if and only if it is an assertible, and the Principle and
the Chrysippean thesis will be, pro tanto, equivalent. But there are other ways
of interpreting the word ‘proposition’.
There is a third point of difference between Chrysippus’ thesis and
the modern Principle of Bivalence. It may be introduced like this. Some
properties, we tend to think, belong to their owners timelessly, whereas
others are timed. Individual numbers, say, own their properties—or at any
rate, their arithmetical properties—timelessly: if you hear that the number 27
is a cube, you do not ask when or for how long. It is not a cube at a time, nor
for a time, nor even for ever and ever. Individual bodies, on the other hand,
have many of their properties—for example, their colours—at a time or for a
time: if an individual item is coloured thus-and-so, it is coloured thus-and-so
at a certain time, and for a certain time; you may ask ‘For how long was his
nose red?’, ‘When will the lawns be green again?’, and in principle there will
be an answer. (Not, perhaps, in all cases? ‘The French flag is red, white and
blue’—there is no ‘when’ to the matter. But then the French flag is not an
individual item.) The colour-values of individual items are timed.
Are the truth-values of individual items timeless, like arithmetical proper-
ties, or timed, like colour-values? The Principle of Bivalence works—or is
generally taken to work—with timeless notions of truth and falsity. In the
Chrysippean thesis—and in ancient logic quite generally—truth-values are
timed: you may ask when, or for how long, an item is true or false; and in
principle you will get an answer. The point emerges casually from a number
of ancient texts. For example, Sextus remarks of ‘the logicians’ that
they say that the determinate assertible, ‘This man is sitting’ or ‘This man is walking’
is then true when the predicate—i.e. to sit or to walk—holds of the item which falls
under the demonstrative.
(M viii 100)¹²
¹² καὶ δὴ τὸ ὡρισμένον τοῦτο ἀξίωμα, τὸ οὗτος κάθηται ἢ οὗτος περιπατεῖ, τότε φασὶν
ἀληθὲς ὑπάρχειν ὅταν τῷ ὑπὸ τὴν δεῖξιν πίπτοντι συμβεβήκῃ τὸ κατηγόρημα, οἷον τὸ
καθῆσθαι ἢ τὸ περιπατεῖν.