Bivalence Disputed 21
off—and the rest of us may think it cruelly unlikely. But that isn’t to the
point: the point is that—whatever we may think about it—the future of the
festival hasn’t yet been decided. The sun will rise over Aix: that is perfectly
determined. Will it rise over a city in festival attire? That is not yet fixed. So
there is, as yet, no fact of the matter about the festival of Aix-en-Provence.
And where there is no fact of the matter, there there is no truth and no falsity.
Not, of course, that the whole of the future is in that way contingent or up
in the air. On the contrary, innumerable future items are already fixed, and
many have been fixed from all eternity. The future of the natural world is
rough-hewn, and its general development is fixed. Much of the future of any
man is fixed; and of those items which are unfixed for me now, most—or
perhaps all—will get fixed some time before they happen. If it is not now
fixed that there will be a festival in Aix, it will be fixed—one way or the
other—before next July, and before the festival opens (if it does). Contingency
is anything but universal. Nonetheless, there are future contingencies—and
any assertible which deals with such a contingency is neither true nor false.
That, at any rate, is a view which has often been upheld; and sometimes
for the reasons which I have rehearsed.
If an assertible is neither true nor false, then what is it? Some philosophers
have suggested that it has a third truth-value: it is indeterminate, or neutral,
or possible, or the like. No such notion is found in any ancient text, where
there are precisely two truth-values, truth and falsity. An item which is neither
true nor false does not have a filmy third value—it has no truth-value at
all. Questions and commands and prayers and hypotheses are all—according
to the Stoics—sayings and complete sayables. None of them is either true
or false. None of them has a third truth-value. So too—according to some
philosophers—with certain future assertibles.
So the thesis of bivalence was menaced, in antiquity, by paradoxical
assertions, none of which—according to some philosophers—is ever either
true or false; and by vague assertions, some of which—according to some
philosophers—are never either true or false; and by future assertions, some
of which—according to some philosophers—are sometimes neither true
nor false.
In On Fate, Cicero places Chrysippus’ thesis in the context of an argument
over fatalism and the future. In particular, he sets Chrysippus against Epicurus:
Chrysippus strains every sinew to persuade us that every assertible is either true or
false. For just as Epicurus feared lest, should he concede this, he would have to
concede that whatever happens happens by fate (for if one or the other is true from