DIVINE ACTION
— 220—
has understood creation as a free and intentional
divine act that calls the world into being and con-
tinuously sustains its existence. There are four ele-
ments in this account. First, creation is a free divine
act in the sense that it does not follow necessarily
from the divine nature; God could exist without
the world in undiminished fullness of being. God
chooses to create not because God must have the
creature, but because it is good for the creature to
be. The act of creation, therefore, is an expression
of generosity and love. Second, creation is an in-
tentional action insofar as God brings the world
into existence knowingly and purposefully. These
first two claims distinguish classical accounts of
creation from emanationist accounts, such as that
of the neo-platonic philosopher Plotinus (205–270
C.E), according to which the perfection of being in
God necessarily overflows into a progression of di-
minishing forms of existence. Third, perhaps the
most striking feature of this theological view is that
God’s creative act accounts for the very being of
the creature. There is no pre-existing unformed
“stuff” that constrains and shapes God’s creative
choice. God creates from nothing (ex nihilo), that
is, apart from God’s creative act, nothing at all
would exist other than God. Finally, the world that
God creates has no power to continue to exist on
its own. Finite things depend at every moment on
a divine creative action that continuously sustains,
or conserves, their existence. Creation, therefore, is
not a one-time event completed at some moment
long ago but rather is an ongoing active relation-
ship of God to the whole finite world throughout
its history. This stands in contrast to the view asso-
ciated with eighteenth century deism, which re-
sponded to the rise of Newtonian mechanics by ar-
guing that the creator establishes the structure of
the world and then leaves it to exist and to oper-
ate on its own.
This way of thinking about God’s action at the
foundation of the world will pervasively shape
one’s interpretation of traditional talk about God’s
action within its history. On this account of cre-
ation, every event in the world depends upon the
action of God; it will be true to say that God acts
in all things. Theologians have not wanted to con-
clude from this, however, that God is the only ef-
fective cause or agent, or that created causes
merely appear to bring about effects in the world
while God alone directly produces all change.
Views of this sort came to be called occasionalism,
because they regard created causes merely as oc-
casions for the action of God in bringing about the
effect. In rejecting this view, Thomas Aquinas (c.
1225–1274) affirmed that God gives created things
active and passive causal powers of their own, that
is, the capacity to affect other things and to be af-
fected by them. God is always the primary cause
who directly sustains the existence of every crea-
ture, but God also chooses to act indirectly
through the operation of created, or secondary,
causes. This provides a further sense in which
events in the world may be understood as God’s
acts, namely, that God acts by means of the order
of nature to produce effects in the world. This
mode of divine action is analogous to indirect
human action in which various means are used to
achieve one’s ends. Aquinas notes that when the
artisan uses a hammer and chisel to shape stone,
the effect is produced both by the tools and by the
human agent who wields them, though the two
causes operate on different levels. Similarly, God
acts by means of the entire network of causal rela-
tions that constitutes the created world. God’s en-
gagement with finite causes goes much deeper, of
course, than the involvement of human agents
with the tools they use. For God directly sustains
the very existence of the finite cause (traditionally
called divine conservation) and, on some accounts,
empowers it to act as it does (traditionally called
divine concurrence). Hence, by establishing the
lawful structures of nature and setting the bound-
ary conditions under which they operate, God in-
directly produces the vast range of effects that to-
gether make up the history of the universe.
Indeed, if the universe were a causally closed, de-
terministic system, then everything that happens
would be an indirect act of God. On the other
hand, if the universe includes moments of indeter-
ministic openness within its structure (e.g., either
as chance or as self-determining freedom), then
God will set the direction of cosmic history but not
necessarily specify all of its details.
The classical conception of creation that un-
derlies this account of divine action is by no means
the only view found in the theistic traditions. Proc-
ess, or neo-classical, theologies reflect a contem-
porary alternative approach that has different im-
plications for divine action in the world. These
theologians make use in various ways of the
thought of Alfred North Whitehead (1861–1947)
and Charles Hartshorne (1897–2000). Within