
Humanistic logic
177
English
logicians and their technically refined formal
logic
for opprobrium,
establishing them as the main butt of humanist ribaldry and vituperation
down
to the seventeenth century.
19
Humanist criticism of
logic,
then, begins with criticism of the profess-
ional logician, and the structuring of the university curriculum around the
terminology
and the technical problems
of
the
logic
course. Early humanist
educators are unanimous in their insistence on the comparatively modest
role
logic
ought to play within a student's total training. Associated with
this disparagement
of
traditional
logic
instruction is a general commitment
on the part
of
humanist educators to initiating language study with a study
of
grammar which attends to the subtleties
of
the Latin language rather than
to the terminology and technical niceties which would be required at a later
stage
if
the student were to pursue
logical
studies into their higher specialist
reaches. Thus early humanist treatises on education, like Vergerio's De
ingenuis moribus
20
make passing reference to the need for competence in the
trivial
arts
of
grammar,
logic
and rhetoric, but insist upon eloquence and in-
depth familiarity with the literary works of antiquity as the basis for
true
learning.
21
The same kind
of
emphasis is to be found less programmatically
in a work like Bruni's AdPetrum Paulum Histrum dialogus ('Dialogue for Pier
Paolo
Vergerio').
Celebrating Salutati's formative influence, Bruni writes
of
his approach to Latinity:
Neither are you one
of
those, in my
view,
who takes pleasure in vain loquacity. Nor
do you incite us in
that
direction, but
rather
to speak gravely, steadily, and so
that
we
seem to
understand
and feel what we speak. To which end, your desire is
that
we
should have a sound grasp on
that
about which we dispute, not simply in itself, but
so
that
we have an understanding
of
its consequences, its antecedents, its causes, its
effects,
and everything in short which relates to the
matter
in hand. For no debater
who
is ignorant of these things
will
be able to dispute without appearing inept.
22
This
sensitivity to language is not, in Bruni's
view,
to be confused with the
preoccupations of contemporary dialecticians. They, on the contrary,
distort
that
subject, as all scholastic study distorts and deforms
true
learning:
But
what about dialectic, which is a most essential art for conducting disputations?
Does
dialectic maintain a flourishing reign, subjected to no calamitous defeat in this
19.
Ibid., p. 38 (1.7):
'Dyalectica
pars
esse
potest,
utique
terminus
non est; et
potest
pars
esse
matutina,
non
serótina.'
For
Petrarch's
hostility
to
English
logic
and
logicians,
see ibid., pp.
35-38
(1.7) passim.
20. On
Vergerio
see, in
this
context,
Robey
1980. 21. See, for
instance,
Robey
1980, p. 47.
22. Prosatori latini 1952, p. 52:
'Ñeque
enim
tu es, ut
opinor,
quern
garrulitas
vana
delectet,
neque
ad
earn
rem nos
cohortaris;
sed ut
graviter,
ut
constanter,
ut
denique
ita
verba
faciamus,
ut ea
quae
dicimus
sapere
atque
sentiré
videamur.
Itaque
tenenda
probe
res est, de qua
disputare
velis;
nec ea
solum,
sed
consequentium,
antecedentium,
causarum,
effectuum,
omnium
denique
quae
ad
earn
rem
pertinent
habenda
cognitio.
His
enim
ignoratis
nemo
disputator
poterit
non
ineptus
videri.'
Cambridge Histories Online © Cambridge University Press, 2008