
Traditional logic
161
level;
and his opponents, who included Fernando de Enzinas nearly two
centuries later, argued
that
there
were parts, which were bound together by
syncategorematic acts, the mental correlates
of
syncategorematic terms.
115
This
topic did not altogether disappear during the sixteenth century, for it is
discussed by Martinus Smiglecius in his Logica;
116
and in Robert Pinke's list
of
questions on
logic,
metaphysics and ethics published in 1680 for the use of
Oxford
students, one of the logic questions was 'Is a mental proposition a
simple quality?'
117
The
other question popularised by Gregory of Rimini had to do with
complexe significabilia, i.e., 'propositions' in the sense adopted by some
modern philosophers.
118
According to medieval and post-medieval
logicians,
a proposition was an indicative sentence capable of being
true
or
false
which was the object
of
an act
of
assertion. As such it was firmly tied to
a particular occasion of utterance or thought. The question then arose
whether
there
was something which propositions signified, or something
which
was named by the dictum in an accusative and infinitive construction,
such as 'Petrum legere' in 'Verum est Petrum legere.' Gregory of Rimini
(following
Adam Wodeham) postulated complexe signijicabilia to
fulfil
this
function. He described them as eternal beings, neither mental nor physical
nor yet identical with God, which were at once the significates
of
indicative
sentences, the bearers of
truth
and falsity and the objects of knowledge or
belief
One opponent of Gregory's
view
was
Jean
Buridan, and many
subsequent authors including Paul of Venice followed Buridan in arguing
that
propositions could only have significates in so far as their subject terms
picked
out some objects in the world. Such a
view
has many difficulties,
particularly because many propositions
will
turn
out to have no adequate
significate.
Another
view
opposed to
that
of Gregory is found in some
Parisian authors, including Enzinas. He argued
that
propositions have no
significates
in the sense of things named or referred to. Instead they signify
aliqualiter; they function as syncategorematic
rather
than
categorematic
terms.
119
In accordance with this interpretation Enzinas recommended
replacing accusative and infinitive constructions with a
'that'
clause. Thus
'
"Human beings are animals" signifies human beings to be animals' should
be rewritten as ' "Human beings are animals" signifies
that
human beings
are animals', which removes the temptation to interpret the dictum as a
115.
For
details
of the
discussion,
see
Ashworth
1981b.
See
also
Nuchelmans
1980, pp.
27-44,
94—101.
116.
Smiglecius
1658, pp.
453-6.
See
also
John
of St
Thomas
1930, pp.
150-7.
117.
Pinke
1680, p. 12.
118. For
details
of the
discussion
see
Ashworth
1978c.
See
also
Nuchelmans
1980, pp.
45-73.
119.
Enzinas
1528, f.
xxxv
rb
~
va
.
Cambridge Histories Online © Cambridge University Press, 2008