sible measure is based on a theory that goes back to Edgeworth; this
measure too is independent from risks and uncertainty.)
17
Thus the classical
measure is not to be confused with the von Neumann–Morgenstern mea-
sure of utility, which is based on consistent choices over lotteries (various
combinations of probability weighted alternatives). (Perhaps we can say
more on this later.)
18
Second, in setting up the correspondence rules so that we can add the
utility measures of distinct individuals, it is not necessary that we be able to
compare the levels (absolute levels) of the well-being of these individuals.
Unit comparability suffices; level comparability is unnecessary. (Full compa-
rability = level plus unit comparability.) Since we are maximizing the sum
of well-being, all that matters is how much (by how many units) each indi-
vidual goes up or down, from where they are, as a result of realizing the
various feasible alternatives. Whether individual A, say, goes up or down n
units from a level higher or lower than the level of B does not matter, as-
suming unit comparability. The institution or policy or action that leads to
the largest net increase (balance of +’s and −’s) from the present situation
will maximize utility over those alternatives.
19
[ 402 ]
appendix
17. [In A Theory of Justice, rev. ed., section 49, p. 282, Rawls says the following: —Ed.
“There are several ways of establishing an interpersonal measure of utility. One of
these (going back at least to Edgeworth) is to suppose that an individual is able to distin-
guish only a finite number of utility levels. A person is said to be indifferent between alter-
natives that belong to the same discrimination level, and the cardinal measure of the utility
difference between any two alternatives is defined by the number of distinguishable levels
that separate them. The cardinal scale that results is unique, as it must be, up to a positive
linear transformation. To set up a measure between persons one might assume that the
difference between adjacent levels is the same for all individuals and the same between all
levels. With this interpersonal correspondence rule the calculations are extremely simple.
In comparing alternatives we ascertain the number of levels between them for each indi-
vidual and then sum, taking account of the pluses and minuses. See A. K. Sen, Collective
Choice and Social Welfare (San Francisco: Holden-Day, 1970), pp. 93f; for Edgeworth, see
Mathematical Psychics (London: Kegan Paul, 1888), pp. 7–9, 60f.”]
18. [See Rawls, A Theory of Justice, rev. ed., section 49, pp. 283–284, for a discussion of
the von Neumann–Morgenstern definition of utility and problems with interpersonal
comparisons of utility. —Ed.]
19. When economists speak of “adding utilities at the margin” they mean something
like this, and precisely this if we suppose that the gains and losses (measured in goods and
services) are sufficiently small so that the marginal utility of each individual stays approxi-
mately constant over the whole interval of possible gains and losses measured in goods
and services, etc. [This sentence was crossed out in Rawls’s handwritten lecture notes.
—Ed.]
Copyright © The President and Fellows of Harvard College
EXAM COPY
EXAM COPY
EXAM COPY
EXAM COPY
EXAM COPY
EXAM COPY
EXAM COPY