Certainly given the many elements in our nature, we need some such
governing or regulative principle. We have appetites, affections, and pas-
sions of various kinds, some more directly concerned with other persons,
some more directly with ourselves. These appetites, affections, and passions
focus on means to certain ends—states of affairs or whatever—and do not,
as such, take into account the wider effects on other persons generally.
These springs of conduct are, let’s say, narrowly focused, whether the focus
is on other persons or on ourselves. None of these springs of conduct can
provide a governing or regulative principle. This follows from the nature of
appetites, affections, and passions. They do not embody a reasonable or
rational principle by which self-government or self-regulation is possible.
Butler illustrates this by the example of the animal enticed into the baited
trap by the prospect of gratifying its hunger. Were we to behave in similar
fashion, contrary to the affection for ourselves expressed by the principle of
reasonable self-love, we would be acting wrongly as well. Butler uses this
example to exemplify the general idea of supremacy: the idea of how one
principle in our nature can be governing—have authority rather than
merely influence—over other elements in our nature.
(3) Next, I believe Butler holds that reasonable self-love is not the au-
thoritative principle of our nature, although he is anxious to maintain that,
in the long run at least, and given the moral government of God, there is
no essential conflict between the authority of conscience and reasonable
self-love. His view of ostensible conflict I shall postpone until later. But it is
easy to see that reasonable self-love, although a general affection in the
sense that it regulates particular appetites, affections, and passions, is an af-
fection for ourselves. The object of reasonable self-love is always partial: it
concerns the good of but one person among many. And so it cannot pro-
vide a principle suitable for our being a law unto ourselves as a member of
society.
The same is true of benevolence: benevolence is likewise often a gen-
eral affection (as self-love is) in that it regulates particular affections for
other persons’ good. This is the case when benevolence takes the form of
public spirit, or love of country (patriotism), and the like. But whereas the
persons who are the concern of reasonable self-love are always well-de-
fined—namely the very person who is moved by self-love—the persons
who are the concern of benevolence shift and vary, and criss-cross, in all
sort of ways from person to person. C. D. Broad suggests that Butler means
[ 429 ]
Five Lectures on Joseph Butler
Copyright © The President and Fellows of Harvard College
EXAM COPY
EXAM COPY
EXAM COPY
EXAM COPY
EXAM COPY
EXAM COPY
EXAM COPY