beings to know what this essence is (Lect. 19. 101). Matter, indeed, can exist
without any form at all. Matter and form are really distinct, and it is well
within the power of God to create and conserve both immaterial form and
formless matter, each of them individuated in their own right.
Actual material substances are composed of both matter and form: here
Scotus agrees with Aristotle and Aquinas. Socrates, for instance, is a human
individual, composed of individual matter and an individual form of
humanity. Scotus gives a novel account, however, of the way in which
the individual substance and its matter and form are themselves individu-
ated. For Aquinas, the form of humanity is an individual form because it is
the human form of Socrates, and Socrates is individuated by his matter,
which in turn is individuated by being designated, or marked oV as a
particular parcel of matter (materia signata). For Scotus, on the other hand,
the form is an individual in its own right, independently of the matter of
Socrates and the substance Socrates (Ord. 7. 483).
What individuates Socrates is neither his matter nor his form but a third
thing, which is sometimes called his haecceitas, or thisness. In each thing,
Scotus tells us, there is an entitas individualis. ‘This entity is neither matter nor
form nor the composite thing, in so far as any of these is a nature; but it is
the ultimate reality of the being which is matter or form or a composite
thing’ (Ord. 7. 393).
According to Aristotelian orthodoxy, forms themselves neither come
into existence nor go out of existence: it is substances, not forms, that are
the subjects of generation and corruption. Strictly speaking we should say
not that the wisdom of Socrates comes into existence: that is only a
complicated way of saying that Socrates becomes wise. With regard to
the independently individuated substantial forms, in Scotus’ system, by
contrast, one can raise the question how they come into existence, and
whether they come out of nothing. Are they created, or do they evolve
from something pre-existing? Scotus rejects both these options. Forms do
not evolve from embryonic forms, or rationes seminales, as Augusti ne,
followed by Bonaventure, had thought. Postulating such entities does
not answer the question of the origin of forms, since the question would
simply rearise concerning whatever is the new element that distinguishes a
fully Xedged form from an e mbryonic one. On the other hand, we do not
want to say that forms are created; but we can avoid saying that if we
redeWne ‘creation’ not as bringing something into existence out of nothing,
METAPHYSICS
204