not the blue of anything real and so perhaps is an accident without a
substance. But St Thomas’ account seems to fail in its purpose of explaining
the presence of Christ on the altar: for one of the Aristotelian accidents is
location, and so ‘is on the altar’, like ‘is white and round’, simply records
the presence of an accident inhering in no substance and tells us nothing
about the location of Christ. At all events, this particular application of the
concepts of substance and accident would certainly have taken Aristotle by
surprise.
But if Aristotle wou ld be unlikely to countenance accidental forms
existing apart from a substance, he left his followers in some doubt about
the possibility of substantial forms existing apart from matter. Aquinas, like
Aristotle, frequently objects to Plato’s postulation of separated forms; but,
unlike Bonaventure, he rejects universal hylomorphism and regards angels
as pure forms. Unlike the Ideal Bed or the Idea of Good, angels such as
Michael and Gabriel are living, intelligent beings; but so far as metaphysical
status goes, there seems little diVerence between Plato’s Forms and Aqui-
nas’ angels. Typical of the ambiguity in Aquinas’ position is the following
passage from his treatment of creation:
Creation is one way of coming into being. What coming into being amounts to
depends on what being is. So those things properly come into being and are
created, which properly have being. And those are subsistent objects. . . . That to
which being properly belongs, is that which has being—and that is a subsistent
thing with its own being. Forms, and accidents, and the like, are not called beings
because they themselves are, but because by them something else is what it is.
Thus whiteness is only called a being because by it something is white. That is why
Aristotle says that an accident not so much is but is of. So, accidents and forms and
the like, which do not subsist, are rather coexistent than existent, and likewise
they should be called concreated rather than created. What really gets created are
subsistent entities. (ST 1a. 45. 4c)
The passage as quoted is admirable as a statement of forthright Aristote-
lianism against any Platonic reiWcation of forms, whether substantial or
accidental. But in that very passage, in a sentence that I deliberately omitted,
Aquinas divides the subsistent entities, which alone really have being and
are created, into two classes: hylomorphic material substances on the one
hand, and separated substances on the other. But separated substances—
angelic spirits and the like—are, as understood by Aquinas, forms that are
not forms of anything, and his way of conceiving them seems open to all the
METAPHYSICS
198