souls, plus a form of corporeality, Aquinas maintained that the rational
soul was the one and only substantial form of a human being. If there had
been a plurality of forms, he argued, one could not say that it was one and
the same human being who thought, loved, saw, heard, drank, slept, and
had a certain weight and size.
Aquinas believed that the human soul was immaterial and immortal.
The argument that the soul is pure form, uncontaminated with matter, is
presented thus:
The principle of the operation of the intellect, which we call the human soul,
must be said to be an incorporeal and subsistent principle. For it is plain that by his
intellect a human being can know the nature of all corporeal things. But to be able
to know things, a knower must have nothing of their nature in his own nature. If
it did, what it had in its nature would hinder it from knowing other things, as a
sick person’s tongue, infected with a bilious and bitter humour, cannot taste
anything sweet because everything tastes sour to it. If, then, the intellectual
principle had in itself the nature of any corporeal thing, it would not be able to
know all corporeal things. (ST 1a 75. 2)
The thesis of the immateriality of the soul goes hand in hand with the
thesis of the intentional existence of the objects of thought. ‘Prime matter
receives individual forms, the intellect receives pure forms,’ Aquinas says.
That is to say, the shape of the Great Pyramid is its shape, and not the shape
of any other pyramidal object; but the intellectual idea of a pyramid in my
mind is the idea purely of pyramid and not the idea of any particular
pyramid. But if the mind had any matter in it, the idea would become
individual, not universal (1a 75. 5c).
This argument, if successful, shows that the soul does not contain
matter. But does it mean that it can exist in separation from matter—in
separation, for instance, from the body of the person whose soul it is?
Aquinas believes that it does. Intellectual thought is an activity in which
the body has no share; but nothing can act on its own unless it exists on its
own; for only what is actually existent can act, and the way it acts depend s
on the way it exists. ‘Hence we do not say that heat heats, but that a hot
body heats. So the human soul, which is called the intell ect or mind, is
something non-bodily and subsistent’ (1a 75. 2c).
One problem with this argument is that elsewhere Aquinas insists that
just as it is strictly incorrect to say that heat heats, so it is strictly incorrect
MIND AND SOUL
241