
The Logic of Probability 187
happen again now, and we say that it has a high probability. If event B happens infre-
quently, then we think it is unlikely, and we say that it has a low probability.
When we decide that an event happens frequently, we are making a relative judgment,
describing the event’s relative frequency. This is the proportion of time that the event
occurs out of all events that might occur from the population. This is also the event’s
probability. The probability of an event is equal to the event’s relative frequency in the
population of possible events that can occur. An event’s relative frequency is a number
between 0 and 1, so the event’s probability is from 0 to 1.
REMEMBER The probability of an event equals the event’s relative frequency
in the population.
Probability is essentially a system for expressing our confidence that a particular ran-
dom event will occur. First, we assume that an event’s past relative frequency will con-
tinue over the long run in the future. Then we express our confidence that the event will
occur in any single sample by expressing the relative frequency as a probability
between 0 and 1. For example, I am a rotten typist, and I randomly make typos 80% of
the time. This means that in the population of my typing, typos occur with a relative
frequency of .80. We expect the relative frequency of my typos to continue at a rate of
.80 in anything I type. This expected relative frequency is expressed as a probability:
the probability is .80 that I will make a typo when I type the next woid.
Likewise, all probabilities communicate our confidence. If event A has a relative fre-
quency of zero in a particular situation, then the probability of event A is zero. This
means that we do not expect A to occur in this situation because it never does. But if
event A has a relative frequency of .10 in this situation, then A has a probability of .10:
Because we expect it to occur in only 10% of our samples, we have some—but not
much—confidence that A will occur in the next sample. On the other hand, if A has a
probability of .95, we are confident that it will occur: It occurs 95% of the time in the
population, we expect it in 95% of our samples, and so our confidence is at .95 that it
will occur now. At the most extreme, an event’s relative frequency can be 1: It is 100%
of the population, so its probability is 1. Here, we are positive it will occur in this situa-
tion because it always does.
All possible events together constitute 100% of the population. This means that the
relative frequencies of all events must add up to 1, so the probabilities must also add up
to 1. Thus, if the probability of my making a typo is .80, then because ,
the likelihood that I will type error-free words is
Understand that except when equals either 0 or 1, it is up to chance whether a partic-
ular sample contains the event. For example, even though I make typos 80% of the time,
I may go for quite a while without making one. That 20% of the time I make no typos has
to occur sometime. Thus, although the probability is that I will make a typo in each
word, it is only over the long run that we expect to see precisely 80% typos.
People who fail to understand that probability implies over the long run fall victim
to the “gambler’s fallacy.” For example, after observing my errorless typing for a while,
the fallacy is thinking that errors “must” occur now, essentially concluding that errors
have become more likely. Or, say we are flipping a coin and get seven heads in a row.
The fallacy is thinking that a head is now less likely to occur because it’s already
occurred too often (as if the coin says, “Hold it. That’s enough heads for a while!”).
The mistake of the gambler’s fallacy is failing to recognize that whether an event
occurs or not in a sample does not alter its probability because probability is deter-
mined by what happens “over the long run.”
.80
p
p 5 .20.
1 2 .80 5 .20