7 The Britannica Guide to Statistics and Probability 7
88
then P(A) = 0, and if the complement of A contains finitely
many elements, then P(A) = 1. As a consequence of the
deceptively innocuous axiom of choice (which says that,
given any collection C of nonempty sets, there exists a rule
for selecting a unique point from each set in C), one can
show that many finitely additive probabilities consistent
with these requirements exist. However, one cannot be
certain what the probability of getting an odd number is,
because that set is neither finite nor its complement finite,
nor can it be expressed as a finite disjoint union of sets
whose probability is already defined.
It is a basic problem, and by no means a simple one, to
show that the intuitive notion of choosing a number at
random from [0, 1], as described above, is consistent with
the preceding definitions. Because the probability of an
interval is to be its length, the class of events M must con-
tain all intervals. To be a σ-field it must contain other sets,
however, many of which are difficult to describe simply.
One example is the event in equation (14), which must
belong to M in order that one can talk about its probabil-
ity. Also, although it seems clear that the length of a finite
disjoint union of intervals is just the sum of their lengths,
a rather subtle argument is required to show that length
has the property of countable additivity. A basic theorem
says that there is a suitable σ-field containing all the inter-
vals and a unique probability defined on this σ-field for
which the probability of an interval is its length. The
σ-field is called the class of Lebesgue-measurable sets, and
the probability is called the Lebesgue measure, after the
French mathematician and principal architect of measure
theory, Henri-Léon Lebesgue.
In general, a σ-field need not be all subsets of the sample
space S. The question of whether all subsets of [0, 1] are
Lebesgue-measurable turns out to be a difficult problem