TIME:RELIGIOUS AND PHILOSOPHICAL ASPECTS
— 897—
of a “supposition or imagination of time” (Sorabji,
p. 237). In the same vein, Aquinas stated:
God is before the world by duration. The
term ‘duration’ here means the priority of
eternity, not of time. Or you might say that
it betokens an imaginary time, not time as
really existing, rather as when we speak of
nothing being beyond the heavens, the
term ‘beyond’ betokens merely an imagi-
nary place in a picture we can form of
other dimensions stretching beyond those
of the body of heavens. (Summa Theolog-
ica 1a, 46, 1)
This means that God’s eternity should not be
understood as some sort of everlasting existence of
the same kind as human existence. God’s eternity
is a dimension other than that of human time. For
this reason the biblical statement that God is be-
fore creation should not be understood in a tem-
poral way. It must be admitted, however, that it
seems almost impossible to clarify this nontempo-
ral use of before, although “logically before” must
be a part of the meaning. But if the reality of a spir-
itual world is accepted, it is certainly likely there
are relations that cannot be fully explained or un-
derstood by human beings.
Aquinas compared this view with the relation
between the center and the circumference of a cir-
cle. The relation between the center and the cir-
cumference is the same all the way round; in a
similar manner, God relates in the same way to all
times.
Furthermore, since the being of what is
eternal does not pass away, eternity is
present in its presentiality to any time or
instant of time. We may see an example of
sorts in the case of a circle. Although it is
indivisible, it does not co-exist simultane-
ously with any other point as to position,
since it is the order of position that pro-
duces the continuity of the circumference.
On the other hand, the center of the circle,
which is no part of the circumference, is
directly opposed to any given determinate
point on the circumference. Hence, what-
ever is found in any part of time coexists
with what is eternal as being present to it,
although with respect to some other time it
be past or future. (Summa contra gentiles
1, c. 66)
The reality of the tenses
Since antiquity two images of time have been dis-
cussed: the line made up of stationary points and
the flow of a river. Philosophically speaking, these
images correspond to two positions: “being as
timeless” and “being as temporal.” The two posi-
tions can be found in early Indian thought, for
instance, as held in Brahmanism and Buddhism,
respectively. The different schools in the Brah-
manical tradition have maintained that the ultimate
being is timeless (i.e., uncaused, indestructible, be-
ginningless, and endless). Buddhists, on the other
hand, have claimed that being is instantaneous and
that duration is a fiction since according to their
view a thing cannot remain identical at two differ-
ent instants (Balslev, p. 69 ff.).
In classical Greek thought the tension between
the dynamic and the static view of time has been
expressed, for example, by the Aristotelian idea of
time as the number of motion with respect to ear-
lier and later—an idea that comprises both pic-
tures. On the one hand time is linked to motion
(i.e., changes in the world), and on the other hand
time can be conceived as a stationary order of
events represented by numbers. This discussion is
also reflected in Isaac Newton’s (1642–1727) ideas
of time, according to which absolute time “flows
equably without relation to anything external”
(Principia, 1687).
The basic set of concepts for the dynamic un-
derstanding of time are past, present, and future.
After J. M. E. McTaggart’s analysis of time in “The
Unreality of Time” (1908), these concepts (i.e., the
tenses) are called the A-concepts. They are well
suited for describing the flow of time, since the
present time will become past (i.e., flow into past).
The basic set of concepts for the stationary under-
standing of time are before, simultaneously, and
after. Following McTaggart, these are called the B-
concepts, and they seem especially apt for describ-
ing the permanent and temporal order of events.
Philosophers discuss intensively which of the
two conceptions is the more fundamental for the
philosophical description of time. The situation can
be characterized as a debate between two Kuhnian
paradigms: the ideas embodied by the well-
established B-theory, which were for centuries pre-
dominant in philosophical and scientific theories of
time, and the rising A-theory, which in the 1950s
received a fresh impetus due to the advent of the