
642
Problems of knowledge and action
the stars. According to the Fathers, fate was an empty word, a diabolical
deceit designed to
strip
man
of
any awareness
of
personal responsibility for
his actions. Augustine, who had run the gauntlet
of
such theories, hated the
word
'fate' itself: 'abhorremus praecipue
propter
vocabulum, quod non in
re vera consuevit intelligi.'
1
Against Epicurean atheism and Stoic immanen-
tism, he asserted free
will,
the
efficacy
of prayer and the dominion of
providence in the world and in human affairs.
Boethius somewhat softened the psychological, not to mention theoreti-
cal,
aversion of earlier Christian thinkers towards fate. He regarded it as
nothing more
than
the movement and disposition imprinted by the divine
mind onto created beings situated in a providential scheme directed to a
particular end.
2
In De consolationephilosophiae, the masterpiece he composed
in prison, Boethius drew heavily on classical sources to produce a rational
and Christian synthesis of the topics associated with fate, namely fortune
and chance, divine foreknowledge and providence and freedom
of
the
will.
Boethius'
eirenic approach and solutions were an influential
legacy
to the
Middle
Ages
and Renaissance.
Scholasticism,
which had begun to tackle more strictly theological
problems like predestination as early as the
ninth
century with Gottschalk
(d. c. 870) and Anselm,
3
aimed to systematise the whole field. According to
Thomas Aquinas, with whom this process culminated, nothing here below
is
determined by fate, either in the pagan mythological sense or because
subject to astral bodies. No events, even so-called chance occurrences, can
escape God's intelligence and loving
attention
to the secondary causes of
nature
and to human
will.
Even if astral and demonic forces occasionally
affect
and change our understanding (whose functioning is structurally
linked to our sensations), any such influence is indirect and is, in any case,
entirely blocked by the interior decisions taken by free
will.
4
Into
the
general scheme of a providence which maintains the particular mode of
action of the individual
natural,
necessary or free causes, Thomas also
reintroduces the predestination of the elect to paradise and
of
the sinners to
damnation. This provoked much later confusion and, as we shall see, an
indignant refutation by Pomponazzi in his De fato.
5
Apart from these
theological
complications, two further positions trace their philosophical
roots in Christian thought to a
belief
in God's absolute transcendence and
1.
Augustine,
De civitate Dei v.9.
3. See
Gottschalk
1945. For
Anselm,
see De libertate
arbitrii
(c.
1080-5);
De concordia praescientiae et
praedestinationis et
gratiae
Dei cum libera arbitrio
(1107-8).
4.
Thomas
Aquinas,
Summa
theologiae 1, q. 115, aa. 3-6; q. 116, aa. 1-4. For a
comparison
with
Boethius
see
Mauro
1981. 5.
Thomas
Aquinas,
Summa
theologiae 1, q. 22, a. 4; q. 23, a. 5.
Cambridge Histories Online © Cambridge University Press, 2008