
Moral philosophy
327
widest
ranging
and
longest lasting influence
on the
interpretation
of
Aristotle's
Ethics
was
Thomas Aquinas, known
by his
followers
as 'the
Expositor'.
His
Expositio continued
to be
printed
well
into
the
seventeenth
century
and was
studied
by
humanists
as
well
as
scholastics, Protestants
as
well
as
Catholics.
144
Agostino Nifo praised Thomas' interpretation
of the
Ethics
for its
lucidity, while both
John
Case
and
Theodor
Z
winger
argued
that
Thomas often provided more help
in
understanding Aristotle's
meaning than recent commentators
who
were more learned
and
could read
the text
in
Greek.
145
Many humanists
did
of
course find Thomas' style
and
terminology
repellent. Denys Lambin,
for
example, even when citing
Thomas with approval, translated
his
scholastic Latin into more palatable
Ciceronian
vocabulary.
146
But
even those who criticised
his
interpretations
had clearly read
his
commentary with considerable care
and
still thought
it
worthwhile
to
argue against him.
147
Scholastic
commentaries
on the
Nicomachean Ethics continued
to be
written
as
well
as
read during
the
Renaissance.
In 1509 two
philosophers
teaching
at the
University
of
Paris, Nicolas Dupuy
and
Gilbert Crab,
published
Jean
Buridan's commentary
on
books
1—vi
along with their
own
quaestiones
on
books
vii—x.
148
Johannes Versor, Petrus Tartaretus and
John
Mair
in
their commentaries
on the
Ethics
all
adopted
the
typical scholastic
format
of
quaestiones, dubitationes, responsiones
and
conclusiones, while
Antonius
Silvester broke Aristotle's arguments down into syllogisms,
enthymemata
and
corollaries.
The
Cursus Conimbricensis
on the
Ethics, first
published
in
1593, still retained many scholastic features, such
as the use of
quaestiones
and the
division
of the
disputationes into numbered articuli
and
conclusiones.
1A9
144. Cranz
1978; Pagden 1975, p. 309. On Thomas' interpretation of Aristotle's
Ethics,
see Papadis 1980
and Elders 1984. For Thomas' influence in the Renaissance, see Poggio Bracciolini 1984-, 1, p. 16:
'Expositorem [Aristotelis] habeo Thomam de Aquino, virum egregium et facundum prout patitur
pondus rerum'; Francesco Maturanzio's
Огайо
in
laudem Divi Thomae Aquinatis
in Zappacosta
1984, pp.
112-25;
see
also
Gray
1965; Kristeller 1967a; J. W. O'Malley, 1974.
145.
Nifo 1645, p. 49 (De
vera vivendi libértate):
'Thomas dilucidus
eius
[sc. Aristotelis] interpres'; Case
1596a,
p. 533: 'Multi hodie cum audiunt nomen Thomae, supercilia statim contrahunt. . .; sed si
isti
serio
unam vel alteram quaestionem in
illo
sine
praeiudicata sententia legerint . . . aurum
splendidissimum forsan se
invenisse
dixerint'; Zwinger 1566, p. 23: '[Thomas Aquinas]
coniectando multa assecutus est, quae caeteri, quantumvis lingua graeca probe instructi, aut
ignorarunt, aut tanquam manifesta neglexerunt.'
146.
Lambin 1558, p. 377 ad vi.12 (1144*29-30): 'D. Thomas. . . hunc locum explicat: "in hoc animi
aspectu atque oculo, id est in solertia ingenerari prudentiam non
sine
virtute"'; cf. Thomas
Aquinas
1934, p. 418 (vi.
10.1273):
'in anima, "huic visui" idest huic cognoscitivo principio scilicet
dinoticae, habitus prudentiae non fit
sine
virtute morali'.
147.
For Ermolao Barbaro's critiques, see Kristeller 1956a, p. 349; see
also
Muret 1789, in, pp. 176 and
195.
148.
Aristotle 1509; on Dupuy and
Crab
see Lohr
1974b,
p. 271 and 1975, pp. 725-6.
149.
Versor 1491; Tartaretus 1514;
Mair
1530; A. Silvester 1517;
Collegium Conimbricense
1612.
Cambridge Histories Online © Cambridge University Press, 2008