Ridling, Philosophy Then and Now: A Look Back at 26 Centuries of Thought
606
focus was now firmly fixed on the nature of human thought and on the
procedures available to it.
Descartes utilized the skeptic’s own arguments to urge a meditative
turning inward. This inward journey was designed to show that each human
being can come to knowledge of his intellectual self and that as he does so he
will find within himself the idea of God, the mark of his creator, the mark that
assures him of the existence of an objective order and of the objective validity
of his rational faculties. The foundation and starting point of Cartesian
knowledge is, for each individual, within himself, in his experience of the
certainty that he must have of his own existence and in the idea of a perfect,
infinite being, in other words, an idea that he finds within himself, of a being
whose essence entails God’s existence, and of whose existence man can thus
be assured on the basis of his idea of God.
Descartes thus preserved and built on Montaigne’s emphasis on self-
consciousness, and this is what marks the changed orientation in philosophy
that constitutes philosophical anthropology in the stricter, second sense. As
the French scientist and religious philosopher Blaise Pascal realized, the
question had now become one of whether man finds within himself the basis
of loyalty to a universal order of reason and law with which his own thought
and will is continuous, or whether he finds, by inner examination, that order,
at least insofar as it can be known, is relative to his feeling, desire, and will.
The attempt to regain an objective order by looking inward apparently
fails with the failure of Descartes’s proofs of the existence of God, proofs that
his contemporaries (even those who, like Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, were
sympathetic to many aspects of the project) were quick to criticize. Reaction
to this failure was twofold. In the work of rationalist philosophers, such as