compact was, in effect, fraudulent, the rich dominating and deceiving the
poor. The central evil was economic inequality, with the rich having as-
sured possessions, the poor having little or nothing. But the poor, not fore-
seeing the consequences, were ready to acquiesce in law and political au-
thority as a remedy for the conflict and insecurity of an agricultural society
without government (SD, 158ff ).
12
The actual form of government established reflects the greater or lesser
inequalities among individuals at the time that political authority is insti-
tuted. If one person is preeminent in power and wealth, that person alone
is elected magistrate and the state is a monarchy. If a number of roughly
equal persons prevail over the rest, there is aristocracy; whereas if fortunes
and talents of all persons are not too unequal, there is democracy. In each
case, political authority added political inequality to the kinds of inequality
that already existed (SD, 171f ).
The last pages of the Second Discourse sketch “the progress of inequal-
ity,” as Rousseau calls it, in three stages: “the establishment of the law and
of the right of property was the first stage, the institution of the magistracy
the second, and the third and last was the changing of legitimate power
into arbitrary power. So that the status of rich and poor was authorized by
the first epoch, that of powerful and weak by the second, and by the third
that of master and slave, which is the last degree of inequality and the limit
to which all the others finally lead, until new revolutions dissolve the gov-
ernment altogether or bring it closer to its legitimate institution” (SD, 172).
So things finally come full circle: humanity begins with the state of na-
ture (the first of the four cultural stages before civil society) in which all are
equal. It arrives finally at the ultimate stage of inequality where all become
equals again because they are nothing, and there is no longer any law except
the will of the master, who is ruled by his passions: “The notions of good and
the principles of justice [which arose with the compact of government] van-
ish once again. Here everything is brought back to...anewstate of nature
different from the one with which we began, in that the one was the state
of nature in its purity; and this last is the fruit of an excess of corruption”
(SD, 177).
2. In the last paragraph of the Second Discourse Rousseau, referring to
the vanities, vices, and miseries of contemporary civilization he has just de-
[ 203 ]
The Social Contract: Its Problem
12. Other modes of origin of government—conquest, subjection to an absolute mas-
ter (what Locke referred to as royal absolutism), paternal authority, subjection to tyr-
anny—Rousseau rejects as very unlikely (SD, 161–168).
Copyright © The President and Fellows of Harvard College
EXAM COPY
EXAM COPY
EXAM COPY
EXAM COPY
EXAM COPY
EXAM COPY
EXAM COPY