KANT’S ANTI-IMPERIALISM 203
laws progressively lose their vigor, and a soulless despotism, after it has
destroyed the seed of good, finally deteriorates into anarchy.” (8:367)
Sociologically, then, the existence of human differences (especially, for
Kant, religious and linguistic differences) is politically advantageous; thus,
the fact of difference should be celebrated by any friend of political free-
dom. But such differences can also “bring with them”, Kant concedes,
“the propensity to mutual hatred and pretexts for war”. Moreover, as he
knew, imperialism can undo by force, by stamping out or by subverting
religious and linguistic difference, what (we can speculatively presume)
“nature” uses to keep human groups from forming a despotic universal
state. Kant hoped that a combination of selfish motives (the spirit of
commerce and the power of money) and a “gradual approach of human
beings to greater agreement in principles”, most crucially that of the law
of nations and cosmopolitan right, would make imperialism and aggres-
sive state actions ethically unacceptable to a more enlightened global
community (8:368). The diversity of languages and religions would then
remain and would serve a key purpose in securing political freedom and
cosmopolitan justice, while its potentially damaging effects might be mit-
igated for both selfish and moral reasons.
43
Kant realized that this consti-
tuted a hope, and (as we saw in the last chapter) he staked this hope not
upon a guarantee of political progress but upon a realizable goal toward
which individuals could and should work.
It is clear that while Kant views hunting and pastoralist peoples as
social groups who live freely chosen, human ways of life, he does not also
consider them to be political societies. In this respect, he exemplifies
much of the history of theorizing civil life, which is, by both linguistic
and philosophical tradition, the sedentary life of a polis. As I have argued,
there is a strong assumption that runs throughout much of the tradition
of European political thought that fundamentally links agrarianism and
the political (or civil) life. The social contract tradition often reinforced
this link by treating nonsettled peoples as perfect examples of individuals
in a state of nature who ought to leave their condition to create a civil
(and presumably a settled, agrarian) life. In Kant’s understanding, many
New World peoples are social but noncivil humans. This would seem to
indicate that they are identical to the individuals of Kant’s state of nature,
for, in his social contract account, the state of nature can be, and often is,
social; what ultimately defines this condition is that it is not civil. Kant
did not believe, however, that the hunters and pastoralists of his day were
identical to the noncivil, natural humans of his social contract narrative,
as I later argue for three reasons. In this respect, in the tradition of mod-
ern political thought, Kant was a most unusual social contract theorist.
What follows from this is that hunting and pastoralist peoples are not
under a categorical duty to transform their societies on the model of