KANT’S ANTI-IMPERIALISM 181
table of contents of which indicates a distinction among savage, barbaric,
civilized (polic´es), working, and virtuous peoples; this system of classifica-
tion in part seems to have been influenced by Montesquieu.
10
As we have
seen, Diderot also emphasizes the importance of peoples’ differing land-
use practices. And perhaps most famously, Scottish Enlightenment writ-
ings often employed a similar system of classification—the so-called four-
stage theory of social development—that analyzed hunting, pastoral,
agricultural, and commercial societies.
11
As one would expect, Kant’s view of humanity as cultural agency influ-
ences his conceptualization of human diversity as well. The most salient
differences among groups of humans and, more broadly, among nations
turn not upon biological or environmental differences, but simply upon
the different uses of the situated reason and freedom—the cultural agency—
that define us as creatures with humanity. Kant, in his delineation of
global human diversity, identifies peoples exclusively by their activities as
cultural agents. This stands in contrast to two other strategies of coming
to terms with the diversity of peoples that eighteenth-century ethnogra-
phy presented: (1) dividing up the world’s peoples according to a theory
of biological or intrinsic ability (as race theorists would do en masse in
the nineteenth century, building upon the early development of the con-
cept of race in the eighteenth century, to which Kant himself contrib-
uted); and (2) focusing on environmentally induced characteristics (sloth,
industriousness, and so forth) that were said to be engendered by various
climates. Kant’s account of humanity as cultural agency leads him to treat
the most socially fundamental human activities, those around which en-
tire societies are organized and shaped, as central to an understanding of
the diversity of peoples. Accordingly, Kant presents hunting, pastoralist,
and agrarian pursuits as rationally chosen or sustained activities, not as
biologically (i.e., instinctually or racially) or climatically determined prac-
tices. A crucial consequence of this view is that nomadic peoples do not
lead the ‘natural’ lives of noble (or ignoble) savages, as opposed to the
‘artificial’ lives of the Chinese, the Europeans, or other agriculturalists.
Rather, they lead lives as humans, as cultural agents, and thus they con-
sciously continue to lead and to transform their lives as a result of dis-
tinctively human judgements, which are often, in his view, incommensur-
able and, thus, are not often amenable to universal moral censure. Kant’s
account of human diversity attends to the plurality of distinctively human
judgements—“culture in general”—that individuals and groups make
differently, and for which there often exists no objectively valid, universal
measure of superiority, moral goodness, or excellence.
Although this is not much noted, it is clear that Kant’s categorization
of the diversity of peoples underwent a transformation in his published
writings from the mid-1780s onward. The manner in which he concep-