170 CHAPTER FOUR
ity (i.e., their cultural agency). Finally, Kant’s political thought denotes
the freedom (the one “innate right” of humanity) that makes cultural
agency possible and that any just political order should protect, which
has important implications (as we will see in the following chapter) for
his understanding of international and cosmopolitan justice.
Ultimately, for Kant, humanity (Humanit¨at, Menschheit) and culture
(Kultur) are fundamentally linked concepts. Notwithstanding the other
meanings of these concepts, ‘humanity’ refers most fundamentally to
what Kant views as the basic anthropological fact that humans are beings
who create and/or sustain and transform desires, values, and ideals, in-
scribe their own meanings and idealizations of beauty on to the world,
and draw upon memory, imagination, and skill to orient themselves and
transform their surroundings. Given Kant’s emphasis on culture and free-
dom as integral to the very idea of humanity, I have called his view ‘hu-
manity as cultural agency’. We saw earlier that Diderot’s political thought
is animated by a similar understanding of humanity. As Kant makes clear
in Conjectures on the Beginning of Human History, Religion within the
Boundaries of Mere Reason, and The Metaphysics of Morals, the uses of
reason and freedom that humanity as cultural agency presupposes are
embedded within and partly shaped by humans’ social contexts. In sharp
contrast to the typical (ostensibly Kantian) view of the rarefied human
subject who stands free of all social and cultural attachments, Kant asserts
that ‘humanity’ refers fundamentally to the idea that human beings are
situated within, and also have the powers to transform, their concrete,
empirical surroundings. In our capacity as beings with humanity, we use
our practical reason, not alone and free from all worldly influences, “but
only as subservient to other incentives” (6:28), incentives that are in-
formed by reflections upon our environmental and social surroundings.
Kant writes that the contextual reasoning and freedom that animates cul-
tural agency makes possible “human choice”, a “freedom of choice” (or
“negative freedom”) that we possess as beings with humanity (as op-
posed to an “animal choice” that is driven by instinct alone, or enact-
ments of our “positive freedom” that we make as moral persons when we
act out of our commitment to moral duty alone) (6:213). This sphere of
constitutively human activity is simply “culture in general” (6:392). All
humans, simply because of their humanity, use their reason, freedom,
memory, imagination, skill, and other powers to extend and transform
their cultural lives. Thus, when Kant discusses what differentiates human-
ity (Humanit¨at) from animality, the concept of Kultur is almost always
present. Kant describes the capacities that allow us to draw upon our
surroundings and alter our environments as the “incentives to culture”
that all humans have as beings with humanity (6:27); the social injustices,
such as inequality, that often arise from the plural uses of our distinctively