
< previous page page_280 next page >
Page 280
Most statements in mathematics take the form: ‘if
P,
then
Q
’ meaning ‘if
P
is true, then
Q
is true.’ We
also say ‘
P
implies
Q
’
,
or ‘
P
is a sufficient condition for
Q,
’ or that ‘
Q
is a necessary condition for
P
.’ We
often write ‘
P Q
.’ The letter
P
stands for the assumptions, and the letter
Q
stands for the conclusions.
The statement ‘
Q P
’ is called the
converse
of the statement ‘
P Q
.’ A statement and its converse say
very different things, and the truth or falsity of one does not imply the truth or falsity of the other. For
example, the statement ‘if
n
is a positive number, then
n
2 is a positive number’ is true, but the
converse, ‘if
n
2 is a positive number, then
n
is a positive number,’ is false, as the counterexample
n
=−1
shows. If ‘
P Q
’ and ‘
Q P
’ are both true, then we write ‘
P Q,
’ which is read ‘
P
if and only if
Q
’
often abbreviated to ‘
P
iff
Q
.’ We also say that ‘
P
is a necessary and sufficient condition for
Q
.’
There are two ways to try to prove a statement of the form ‘if
P,
then
Q
.’ The simplest is called a
direct
proof,
and takes the following form: we write down our assumption
P;
we carry out an argument; we
deduce
Q
. An
argument
consists of things we know to be true, perhaps because they were proved
earlier, or because of a definition, or because of what we are allowed to assume in
P
. In addition, we
can write down statements that are deductions from previous statements in our argument. For example,
if ‘
R
or
S
’ is true and I know that
R
is false then I know that
S
must be true. Little arguments such as
this are often described at the beginning of books on discrete mathematics, but are usually easy to pick
up from working through specific proofs. Unfortunately, direct proofs do not always work and then we
have recourse to what are known as
indirect proofs
. These take the following form: assume that
P
is
true; then for the sake of argument assume that
Q
is
false,
i.e., the reverse of what we want. Then
carry out an argument that leads to an assertion contradicting something we know to be true. Because
assuming
Q
false leads to a contradiction, and because statements are either true or false but not both,
it follows that
Q
must really be true. Most arguments in this book are direct, and many mathematicians
have a bias in favour of direct arguments.
There is one type of direct proof that we often use in this book:
proof by induction
. This works for those
statements
P
whose truth is determined by the truth of a sequence of special cases:
P
(0),
P
(1),
P
(2),…,
that is, to prove
P
is true we have to prove that the statements
P(n)
are true for all natural numbers
n
.
The general form a proof by induction is as follows:
•
Base case:
Check first that
P
(0) is true.
•
Induction hypothesis:
Assume that
P(k)
is true.
•
Deduction:
Use the truth of
P(k)
to establish the truth of
P
(
k
+1); it is at this stage we usually have to
do some work.
•
Conclusion:
Conclude that
P(n)
is true for all
n,
from which it follows that
P
is true, as required.
< previous page page_280 next page >