while on the other hand there are signs that have no signiWcant parts.
These simple signs come in two diVerent kinds, names (Int.2.16a20–b5) and
verbs (Int.3.16b6–25): the two are distinguished from each other, we learn,
because a ver b, unlike a noun, ‘signiWes time in addition’, i.e. has a tense.
But in the Categories there is a much richer classiWcation of simple sayings. In
the fourth chapter of the treatise Aristotle has this to say:
Each one signiWes either substance (ousia), or how big, or what sort, or in relation to
something, or where, or when, or posture, or wearing, or doing, or being acted on.
To give a rough idea substance is e.g. human, horse; how big is e.g. four-feet, six-
feet; what sort is e.g. white, literate; in relation to something is e.g. double, half,
bigger than; where is e.g. in the Lyceum, in the forum; when is e.g. yesterday,
tomorrow, last year; posture is e.g. is lying, is sitting; wearing is e.g. is shod, is
armed; doing is e.g. cutting, burning; being acted on is e.g. being cut, being burnt.
(4. 1b25–2a4)
This compressed and cryptic passage has received repeated commentary
and has exercised enormous inXuence over the centuries. These ten things
signiWed by simple sayings are the categories that give the treatise its name.
Aristotle in this passage indicates the categories by a heterogene ous set of
expressions: nouns (e.g. ‘substance’), verbs (e.g. ‘wearing’), and interroga-
tives (e.g. ‘where?’ or ‘how big?’). It became customary to refer to every
category by a more or less abstract noun: substance, quantity, quality,
relation, place, time, posture, vesture, activity, passivity.
What are c ategories and what is Aristotle’s purpose in listing them? One
thing, at least, that he is doing is listing ten diVerent kinds of expression
that m ight appear in the predicate of a sentence about an individual
subject. We might say of Socrates, for example, that he was a man, that
he was Wve feet tall, that he was wise, that he was older than Plato, and that
he lived in Athens in the Wfth century bc. On a particular occasion his
friends might have said of him that he was sitting, wearing a cloak, cutting
a piece of cloth, and being warmed by the sun. Obviously, the teaching of
the Categories makes room for a variety of statements much richer than the
regimented propositions of the Prior Analytics.
The text makes clear, however, that Aristotle is not only classifying
expressions, pieces of language. He saw himself as making a classiWcation
of extra-linguistic entities, things signiWed as opposed to the signs that
signify them. In Chapter 6 we shall explore the metaphysical implications
of the doctrine of the categories. But one question must be addressed
125
LOGIC