358 Qubit measurements, coding, and teleportation
It is clear that in case (a), there is absolute certainty that the qubit measurement will
result in the bit information 1. In case (b), the outcome has equal chances of being
0 or 1. In case (c) the odds on measuring 1 are twice those of measuring 0. In case
(d), the odds are 99% for 0 and 1% for 1. It must be emphasized here that the above
figures concern the measurement outcomes obtained by using the corresponding opera-
tors M
0
, M
1
. Here comes a subtlety: in case (c), for instance, we know that we have a
1/3 chance of measuring 0 when using M
0
. This means that there is a 2/3 chance that
this measurement fails. Likewise, there is a 1/3 chance that the measurement of 1 fails
when using M
1
. But what does “measurement failure” mean? Basically, that whenever
we choose to use a given measurement projector M
m
, the input state is not absolutely
certain of collapsing into the corresponding state |x
m
. It will only happen “successfully”
with probability |x
m
|
2
. If this collapse does not happen (with probability 1 −|x
m
|
2
), then
nothing is measured, and the measurement is, thus, failed. Also, the quantum state col-
lapses into nothingness, which here means qubit annihilation and irreversible loss of its
information. We can mathematically define such an annihilated, informationless state as
|q
=∅.
To clarify the picture, or to alleviate some possible unease with the notions of “suc-
cessful” and “failed” qubit measurements, consider the following (fictitious) physical
analogy, which we have already used in Chapter 17 for POVM measurements.
Compare the qubit |q with a source that has two possible tones, A or B (standing for
the states |0 or |1, respectively), and which are not visible to the eye. Our measurement
consists of determining the color tones by observing this source through a set of two
“magic filters,” called 0, 1(forM
0
, M
1
). As we have seen earlier, such filters have
strange properties. Indeed, filter 0 does not react to tone B, while it makes tone A
visible to the eye, but only with probability p (or |α|
2
). Filter 1 does not react to tone
A, while it makes tone B visible to the eye, but only with probability q = 1 − p (or
|β|
2
). Even stranger here (than the description in Chapter 17) is that the two filters
A, B are of complementary nature, since their probabilities of positive reaction are now
complementary (q = 1 − p). Figure 18.1 shows the eye images obtained in the eight
possible cases, according to the two pure-tone possibilities A or B (but not both) and
their mixture A, B, and the two filter options 0, 1. The observation of a bright spot
indicates a positive, or successful, measurement (seeing something). The absence of a
spot indicates a negative, or failed, measurement (not seeing anything).
Considering first the case of pure tones (A or B), the figure indicates that there are
actually two “successful” measurement outcomes, as characterized by the presence of
the bright spot with nonzero probability. These successes correspond to the two input or
filter cases ( A, 0), (B, 1), which positively identify the tones to be A or B with absolute
certainty ( p = 1forA,orq = 1 − p = 1forB). In the two other cases, ( A, 1), (B, 0),
we never see any spot, or the measurement is always “failed.” But here comes a subtlety:
if we know prior to the measurement that the color tones are pure, the failed measurement
is also a positive indication. Indeed, a failure to measure A means an absolute certainty
that the input is B, and the reverse. The certainty is the same regardless of our filter choice
(0 or 1). In this case, the classical bit measurement from the qubit is 100% accurate. The