Naive Set Theory
31
addition, multiplication, and exponentiation. These theorems hold in arithmetic
provided that p > 1. In the arithmetic of arbitrary cardinal numbers all of the
cancellation laws fail to fold: it suffices to let m = 2, n = 3, and p =
ℵ
0
to obtain a
counterexample. On the other hand, the cancellation laws with respect to addition,
multiplication, and exponentiation hold for the relation <. They follow without
difficulty from the law of trichotomy, which now we state without proof.
Theorem 2.3.11. For arbitrary cardinal numbers m and n, either m ≤ n or n ≤ m.
We now study a few properties of the cardinal numbers
ℵ
0
and c.
(1) c =c+c
:
In fact, let X and Y be intervals (0,1) and [1,2). Then ⏐X
⏐
=
⏐
Y
⏐
=
c
and
⏐
X
∪
Y⏐ = c + c = ⏐
(0,2)
⏐
= c.
(2)
For each natural number
n, n
<
ℵ
0
< c
:
The inequality follows from Theorem 2.1.3.
(3)
For each natural number n, n + c = ℵ
0
+ c = c
:
In fact, c ≤ n + c ≤ ℵ
0
+ c ≤ c + c = c. So, by property 1 and Bernstein’s
theorem, the result follows.
(4)
c = c
·
c
:
Proof: Let X be the set of all points in (0,1]. Then X × X = {(x,y) : x,y ∈
(0, 1]} has power c · c. The assertion is proved as soon as we show that the
sets X and X × X are equipollent.
Let z
∈ (0,1) and (x,y) ∈ X × X.
We write the numbers x, y and z by
nonterminating decimal fractions. Since the representation of our numbers
by means of such decimal fractions is unique, it is necessary to show that
the set of decimal fraction pairs
x, y can be mapped on the set of decimal
fractions
z.
Let the pair of decimal fractions
x
and
y
be given. Now we write
the first x-complex, then the first y-complex, then the second x
-complex,
followed by the second y-complex, etc. Since neither x nor y exhibits only
zeros from a certain point on, the process can be continued without ending
and gives rise to a nonterminating decimal fraction. This decimal fraction
shall be made to correspond to the number pair x,y. Every number pair x,y
thus determines precisely one z; conversely, every z determines exactly one
number pair x,y, and, in fact, precisely that pair which gave rise to z. A
one-to-one correspondence between the number pairs x,y and the numbers
z is thereby established, and this completes the proof.