LEGAL
ANTHROPOLOGY
social
fabric
is
maintained
by
mechanical
soli-
darity.
That
is,
people
are
kept together
by the
similarity
of
their beliefs, attitudes, desires,
be-
haviors,
and
values.
In
other words, societies
are
culturally homogeneous.
Law
comes into
the
picture
when somebody disturbs
the
status quo,
and
the
rest
of the
members
of the
society pun-
ish
the
offender.
In
such cases,
the
collective
action against
the
offender
helps bind
the
other
members
of the
society
together.
Law in
tech-
nologically primitive societies, according
to
Durkheim,
is
entirely penal,
and its
only goal
is
to
punish. From there, societies
and
legal sys-
tems
progress
into
the
kind
of
societies
and le-
gal
systems
we
have
in
technologically advanced
societies, where legal sanctions
are
restitutive
in
nature (restitutive sanctions attempt
to
restore
the
original relationship between
the two
par-
ties;
if
someone steals, restitutive sanctions would
demand
that
he
return
to his
victim what
was
stolen
and
apologize
for the
theft).
In his
gen-
eralizations, Durkheim
has
since been proven
wrong
by a
multitude
of
studies
of the
peoples
in
technologically primitive societies. Also,
his
division
of
legal systems
and
societies
is
unwar-
ranted; there
are
many similarities between
so-
cieties,
and
differences
do not
always obtain
on
the
basis
of
whether they
are
technologically
advanced
or
not.
As far as the
matter
of
legal
sanctions
go, we can see
that
in
technologically
advanced
societies,
we
often
use
punitive sanc-
tions
and do not
rely always
on
restitutive sanc-
tions. Also,
in
many technologically primitive
societies,
restitutive sanctions
are
preferred.
Durkheim's
beliefs
were wholly speculative
in
nature.
Legal scholars
have
also long been interested
in
the
subject
of
legal justice, especially
the
sub-
discipline
of
procedural justice, which
is
con-
cerned
with
how
ideas
of
justice
are
implemented
in
actual laws.
An
early thinker
on the
subject
was
Jeremy Bentham,
who
lived
from
1748
to
1832.
Bentham's
primary interest
was in
proce-
dural
justice. Bentham believed that
the
best laws
were
those that produced
the
greatest utility.
But
his use of the
term
utility
is
different
from
the
usual
use of the
word.
By
utility,
Bentham
re-
ferred
to the
amount
of
pleasure produced
in
relation
to the
amount
of
pain produced
by
something else.
For
Bentham,
a
just
law was one
that
resulted
in the
greatest amount
of
pleasure
and
the
least amount
of
pain.
The
problem
with
this theory
is
that
what
^pleasurable
and
what
is
painful
differs
from
society
to
society,
and
thus
Bentham's
theory cannot
be
applied equally
ev-
erywhere.
Further,
the
idea
that
all
people
ev-
erywhere
are
primarily interested
in
pleasure
for
themselves
as
individuals
is
untrue, since
there
are
many people
who
undergo
painful
experi-
ences
or who
deny themselves pleasures
in or-
der
to
advance
the
interests
of
others
or to
benefit
themselves
or
society
in
general.
A
later
figure
in the field of
procedural jus-
tice,
one who is
ultimately responsible
for the
interest
of
legal anthropologists
in the
subject
of
cultural values
in
law,
is
Josef
Kohler.
For
Kohler,
a
just
law
must reflect
the
values held
by the
people
to
whom
the law
applies.
Roscoe Pound,
an
American
who
lived
from
1870
to
1964, expanded upon Kohler
s
idea.
In-
stead
of
looking
at the
values
held
by the
people
as
a
model
for
just law, Pound said, just
law
must
rest upon
the
values
the
people
say
they want
reflected
in
their law.
In
other
words,
if the ma-
jority
of the
people actually believe
in
something
that
is
perhaps good
for
them individually,
but
bad
for the
group
as
such, then they should want
the law to
reflect
the
best interests
of the
group.
For
example,
if
people
in the
United States each
want
to
drive their
own
cars
at 100
miles
per
hour
on the
highways
so
that they
can get
where
they want
to go
more quickly, they also realize
that
if
everyone drove
at 100
miles
per
hour,
many
more people would
be
killed. Therefore,
they support speed limits that
are
much lower.
Another theory
of
justice
was
developed
by
the
legal anthropologist Leopold Pospisil.
He
discovered
while working
with
the
Kapauku
145