
Epistemology
of the
sciences
707
rather
than
with discovery and investigation; for the goal common to many
of
these treatises,
that
of
showing
how to knit facts and principles together
into a body of rational science, is one
that
cuts across the discovery/
communication distinction. The sixteenth-century literature on ordering
and disposition
of
the sciences is vast. Discussion of axiomatic methods has
already been touched on. Ramist didactic method and the furious polemics
which
surrounded it appear to have had substantial impact in the
epistemology
of
the sciences.
104
A further sixteenth-century development
with
important, but as yet little explored, epistemological implications is
that
of humanist promotion of the use of 'dialectical' methods of
presentation and persuasion
that
concentrate on probable argument
—
argument by analogy, citation of
exempla
and so on —
rather
than
demonstration in the strict Aristotelian sense.
105
The
historiography
of
the sciences undergoes great changes in the course
of
the sixteenth century. To
start
with
there
is a move away from a
conception
of the
arts
and sciences as having emerged fully fledged at the
hands
of
the sages of antiquity towards a
view
of them as gradual products
of
prolonged endeavour.
106
Related to this is a development of awareness
of
the importance
of
social
and cultural factors in the growth
of
knowledge,
the basic traditional historiographic motifs of
successio
and
translatio
studii
being
augmented by speculations about the roles of, for example,
education, printing and the amassment of observations on the growth of
knowledge.
107
Further, by the end of the century
there
is a measure of
awareness
of
progress in the mathematical
sciences
as constituted not merely
by
the development
of new
artifacts and better methods
of
calculation
and
prediction but also by improvement at the theoretical
level.
108
These
historiographical developments are, I suggest, of paramount importance
for
the epistemology
of
the sciences; for their outcome is the emergence in
the seventeenth century of notions of linked practical and theoretical
progress through systematic and collaborative endeavour, notions
that
are
presupposed by the major seventeenth-century programmes for the
advancement of the sciences.
104.
See, for example, Hoppe 1976, pp. 25-32, on its influence on methods of classification of
organisms;
Hannaway 1975 on its role in the constitution of chemistry as a discipline.
105.
On humanist promotion of probable argument and its links with development of discourse in
utramquepartem as a didactic vehicle see
Vasoli
1968a; C.J. R. Armstrong
1976; L.
Jardine
1977
and
in
this volume; Schiffman 1984. On the possible importance of this for the epistemology of the
sciences
see
Vasoli
1974, pp. 637-8; N. Jardine 1979; Dear 1984.
106.
See, for example, P. Rossi 1962; Maravall 1966; A.
Keller
1972.
107.
N. Jardine 1984, ch. 8. 108. Ibid.
Cambridge Histories Online © Cambridge University Press, 2008