
Theories of knowledge
681
incertitudine et
vanitate
scientiarum declamado, which has led him to be listed as
one of the early sceptics of the Renaissance. His book is a diatribe against
every
kind of intellectual activity. He said he was doing this to humble
human pride and lead people to
true
religion.
Very
little actual sceptical
argument occurs, though sceptical sources are used.
25
In less bombastic fashion various theologians, Catholic and
Protestant,
used sceptical arguments to indicate
that
human reason is incapable of
leading men to knowledge of divine
matters
and of metaphysics, and so
they should
turn
to faith. Cardinaljacopo Sadoleto felt he had to oppose this
growing
scepticism about whether anything could be known by rational
means, and defend the classical philosophical tradition.
26
In the circle around Petrus Ramus,
there
was serious discussion of the
import
of
scepticism. One
of
Ramus' friends, Omer Talon, wrote a work in
1548
entitled Académica, presenting Cicero's account of Academic scepti-
cism.
Talon saw scepticism as a justification of Ramus' attacks on Aristotle
and Aristotelianism and as a means of liberating human thought. Then
Talon
added the usual Renaissance sceptical statement of fideism: 'What
then
is to be done? Must we believe nothing without a decisive argument,
must we abstain from approving anything without an evident reason? On
the contrary; in religious
matters
a
sure
and solid faith
will
have more
weight
than
all of the demonstrations of all of the philosophers.'
27
(A
somewhat similar
view
appears in
another
work, Académica, published by
Pedro de Valencia in
1596.)
28
Talon's
efforts led to Ramus being attacked as a new sceptic, and his
movement being seen as dangerous to both philosophy and religion, since it
would
undermine any basis for any
beliefs.
One member of Ramus' circle,
Guy
de Brués, wrote a critique
of
this new scepticism in 1557 in the form of
a dialogue amongst members of the Pléiade, in which some of them argue
for
scepticism and others answer the arguments. The work is not very
exciting
philosophically, but indicates how
important
discussion about
scepticism and how to refute it had become by the middle of the sixteenth
century.
29
One could cite other indications in many other writers. The
really
important
philosophical presentations of scepticism appear almost
simultaneously from two distantly related
authors
in France, Francisco
Sanches,
professor at Toulouse, and his cousin, Michel de Montaigne.
Sanches in his
Quod
nihil scitur, written in 1576 and published in 1581,
presents a very acute scepticism in the form of an intellectual critique of
25.
Popkin
1979, pp. 23-6. 26. Ibid., pp. 26-7. 27.
Cited
ibid., p. 29.
28. Ibid., p. 36. 29. Ibid., pp. 30-1.
Cambridge Histories Online © Cambridge University Press, 2008