
Traditional
natural philosophy
217
colleagues
in
philosophy
at the
Collegio
Romano
to
investigate
the
topic
more thoroughly.
56
Thus,
well
before Galileo's observations
in 1609 of
mountains
on the
moon,
the
ground
had
been prepared
for a
revision
of
medieval
views
on the
material composition
of the
heavens.
57
Such
discussions were
not
without their impact
on
theses relating
to the
four terrestrial elements
and the
qualities
that
characterise them. Medieval
teaching
had
accounted
for
accidental changes
in nature
through Aristotle's
four alterative qualities
(hot,
cold,
wet and dry) and his two
motive qualities
(gravitas and levitas),
explained
in
his
Degeneratione et corruptione and
De
caelo
respectively.
Attempts
to
account
for
fevers
and
other medical phenomena
led
Renaissance physicians
to
make adaptations
in
this doctrine, suggesting,
for
example,
that
coldness might
be the
mere absence
of
heat,
or that there
might
be two
types
of
coldness,
one
real,
as
found
in the
elements,
the
other
privative,
as in
other bodies.
58
Cardano proposed
that
neither coldness
nor
dryness exist
as
such,
but are
merely
the
privation
of
heat
and
wetness
respectively.
59
Telesio thought
of all
four
as
real,
but
maintained
that
wetness
and
dryness
are not
qualities
at
all
—
rather
they
are
substances whose
presence
in a
body make
it
either fluid
or
solid.
60
Scaliger,
on the
other
hand, defended Aristotle's original teaching, arguing
that all
four
are true
qualities, real
and
positive
in the
order
of nature.
61
si verum est, videant Peripatetici, quomodo Aristotelis opinionem de materia caeli defendere
possint. Dicendum enim fortasse erit, caelum non
esse
quintam quandam essentiam, sed mutabile
corpus,
licet minus corruptibile sit, quam corpora haec inferiora.'
56. Menu, Vitelleschi, and Ruggiero all
discuss
the matter. The last presents his conclusions in three
propositions; see Ruggiero 1591, f. 6s
r
: 'Prima propositio. Non
esset
usque adeo improbabile
asserere coelum generabile et corruptibile per mutuam transmutationem cum inferioribus . . .
Secunda
propositio. Multo probabilius est asserere coelum generabile et corruptibile, sed per solam
transmutationem substantialem inter ipsas coeli partes'; f. 6$
v
: 'Tertia propositio. Probabilissimum
tamen est, et probabilius quam superiora, coelum
esse
ingenerabile et incorruptibile, quamquam id
positive demonstrari non potest.' In support of the last proposition,
since
it cannot be
demonstrated, Ruggiero simply argues from the authority of Peripatetics and scholastics in this
matter.
See
also
Benedetti 1585, p. 197. 57. Dales 1980; E.
Grant
1983,
1984b.
58. Galileo
discusses
this question in his early notebooks: see Galilei 1977, pp.
230—4,
dating from
around 1590. Excerpts from the Latin text are given in the following notes.
59. Galilei
1890-1909,1,
p. 160: 'Prima sententia fuit quorumdam antiquorum, apud Plutarchum lib.
De
primo frigido, qui dixerunt frigiditatem
esse
privationem caloris. Horum sententiam secutus
est
Cardanus,
lib. 2
0
De subtilitate, qui idem amrmat etiam de siccitate, quam vult
esse
privationem
humoris.'
60.
Ibid.,
p. 161: 'Tertia sententia est aliorum dicentium, omneshas qualitates
realesesseet
positivas: sed
humorem et siccitatem non
esse
qualitates, sed substantias; idest humorem
esse
substantiam
fluentem; siccitatem vero, substantiam consistentem.' Vitelleschi, in his exposition of this subject-
matter,
attributes this
sententia
to Telesio.
61. Ibid.:
'Quarta sententia, vera, est Aristotelis et omnium Peripateticorum, in t. 8 secundi De
generatione et in 4 Meteororum et alibi, dicentium
omnes
quatuor qualitates
esse
veras, reales, et
positivas: quam sententiam optime tuetur contra Cardanum Scaliger, Exercitationum 18,19, 22, et
Plutarchus.'
Cambridge Histories Online © Cambridge University Press, 2008