Ridling, Philosophy Then and Now: A Look Back at 26 Centuries of Thought
928
The thesis that intentional phenomena are the essence of the mental thus
seems problematic. Its suggestion that the jet-searching missile has a mind or
partakes of the mental, as appeared in the discussion of the criterion of
purposeful behavior, would, to many scholars, appear to be quite implausible.
Nor does it seem that the trouble lies in the limited number of intentional
phenomena found in the missile. Even the lunar-exploration machines, with
all of their flexibility and multiplicity of functions, would not be said by most
analysts to have minds.
It might be possible to save intentionality as the criterion of the mental
by insisting on the presence of such highly sophisticated intentional
phenomena as emotions, daydreams, or amusement, but then one would have
to deny minds to those human beings who lack a sense of humour, never
daydream, or are cold-bloodedly unemotional, which does not seem correct
either. Some progress can be made here if the question is asked whether
intentionality is a necessary condition of all mental phenomena – whether
there are any phenomena that are mental but nonintentional. Examples of a
mental phenomenon that can most plausibly be said to be nonintentional are
sensations, such as feeling pain, which lack both of the aforementioned
characteristics of intentionality – inexistence and referential opacity. A man
cannot feel a pain that, unbeknownst to him, does not exist; if he feels pain,
there must be something he feels. Moreover, if a man feels pain, and the pain
is identified with the effect of a tumour, then he does feel the effect of the
tumour.
Sensations, which thus lack both of the characteristics of intentional
phenomena, are not just an odd counterexample; not only do sensations
comprise a large and central group of mental phenomena, but they also call
attention to an important aspect of many other mental phenomena, viz.,