Ridling, Philosophy Then and Now: A Look Back at 26 Centuries of Thought
960
an external world that contains other bodies of the appropriate sort and with
the appropriate behavior. But for dualists and immaterialists, who hold that
mental phenomena are something irreducibly different from the physical,
there is the further question of whether that something is unique to oneself or
whether there are other instances of it in the world.
Some scholars claim that individuals sometimes have direct awareness
of the conscious states of others, either in telepathic experiences, moments of
empathy, or even in everyday social intercourse. There is, moreover, a
transcendental argument, found in Kant and defended by Strawson, holding
that, unless a person could be confident of the existence of other minds, he
could not be confident of the existence of his own mind. A different line of
reasoning, the so-called argument from analogy, is based upon the similarities
between one’s own body and its behavior, on the one hand, and other human
bodies and their behavior on the other. To pursue the argument, since a mind
is known to be associated with one’s own body, it is reasonable to conclude
that another mind is associated with the body of another person. Finally, there
is the view that the best way to explain the complex behavior of other bodies,
especially their ability to behave rationally and in particular to speak and
communicate information, is to postulate other minds at work.
None of these arguments compels strong conviction, certainly not the
degree of conviction that all persons feel concerning the existence of other
minds. Whether stronger arguments will be found, whether philosophers must
admit that there is a considerable amount of faith required here, or whether
they will reformulate their concepts of the mind in a more Materialistic way to
bring them in closer accord with observable data remains to be seen.