Ridling, Philosophy Then and Now: A Look Back at 26 Centuries of Thought
470
the theory of numbers are declared to be presuppositions for geometry and
mechanics, astronomy, physics, chemistry, biology (including physiology),
and sociology. Each higher level science, in turn, adds to the knowledge
content of the science or sciences on the levels below, thus enriching this
content by successive specialization. Psychology is conspicuously missing in
Comte’s system of the sciences. Anticipating some ideas of 20th-century
Behaviorism and physicalism, Comte assumed that psychology should
become a branch of biology (especially of brain neurophysiology), on the one
hand, and of sociology, on the other. As the “father” of sociology, Comte
maintained that the social sciences should proceed from observations to
general laws, very much as (in his view) physics and chemistry do. He was
sceptical of introspection in psychology, being convinced that, in attending to
one’s own mental states; these states would be irretrievably altered and
distorted. In thus insisting on the necessity of objective observation, he was
close to the basic principle of the methodology of 20th-century Behaviorism.
Among Comte’s disciples or sympathizers were Cesare Lombroso, an
Italian psychiatrist and criminologist, and Paul-Emile Littré, J.-E. Renan, and
Louis Weber.
Despite some basic disagreements with Comte, the 19th-century English
philosopher John Stuart Mill, also a logician and economist, must be regarded
as one of the outstanding Positivists of his century. In his System of Logic
(1843), he developed a thoroughly Empiricist theory of knowledge and of
scientific reasoning, going even so far as to regard logic and mathematics as
empirical (though very general) sciences. The broadly synthetic philosopher
Herbert Spencer, author of a doctrine of the “unknowable” and of a general
evolutionary philosophy, was, next to Mill, an outstanding exponent of a
Positivistic orientation.