Ridling, Philosophy Then and Now: A Look Back at 26 Centuries of Thought
202
this bald statement of his doctrine, but unluckily it is certain that much of the
polemic is concerned with the teaching of Speusippus and Xenocrates. It is
not safe, therefore, to ascribe to Plato statements other than those with which
Aristotle explicitly credits him. We have then to interpret, if we can, two main
statements: (1) the statement that the forms are numbers; and (2) the statement
that the constituents of a number are the great and small and the one.
Light is thrown on the first statement if we recall the corpuscular physics
of the Timaeus and the mixture of the Philebus. In the Timaeus, in particular,
the behavior of bodies is explained by the geometrical structure of their
corpuscles, and the corpuscles themselves are analyzed into complexes built
up out of two types of elementary triangle, which are the simplest elements of
the narrative of Timaeus. Now a triangle, being determined in everything but
absolute magnitude by the numbers that express the ratio of its sides, may be
regarded as a triplet of numbers. If we remember then, that the triangles
determine the character of bodies and are themselves determined by numbers,
we may see why the ultimate forms on which the character of nature depends
should be said to be numbers and also what is meant by the mathematicals
intermediate between the forms and sensible things. According to Aristotle,
these mathematicals differ from forms because they are many, whereas the
form is one, from sensible things in being unchanging. This is exactly how the
geometer’s figure differs at once from the type it embodies and from a visible
thing. There is, for example, only one type of triangle whose sides have the
ratios 3:4:5, but there may be as many pure instances of the type as there are
triplets of numbers exhibiting these ratios; and again, the geometrical triangles
that are such pure instances of the type, unlike sensible three-sided figures,
embody the type exactly and unchangingly. A mathematical physicist may
thus readily be led to what seems to be Plato’s view that the relations of