Ridling, Philosophy Then and Now: A Look Back at 26 Centuries of Thought
173
properties of the atoms is a necessary consequence of the idea that atoms are
not subject to internal change; for the changeless can never be a subject of
experimentation. The great weakness of the mechanistic concept of immutable
atoms was that it forced the analyzing experiments to stop at the atoms; but
this weakness could reveal itself only after, in the course of the further
development of science, the fundamentally experimental character of human
knowledge had become evident.
This weakness, in fact, was precisely one of the reasons why Aristotle
rejected the Atomism of Democritus, viz., that the latter had postulated atoms
that were not subject to change. For Aristotle the very essence of matter was
its being subject to change; hence to him the concept of immutable atoms was
a contradiction in terms.
Aristotle’s criticism of Atomism was clearly directed against its
mechanistic metaphysics, not against its realism. This latter characteristic was
the target, however, of an attack launched by the incomparable 18th-century
epistemologist Immanuel Kant. In a famous argument, known as the antinomy
of the continuum, Kant tried to prove that the acceptance of the reality of
spatial extension, the cornerstone of Atomism, led to contradictions. His
argument can be summarized as follows: It is possible to prove that any
compound must be composed of simple things (for if not, there would be
nothing but composition). On the other hand, it also is possible to prove that
no material thing can be simple, for the very reason that a part of an extended
being is always extended and is thus open to division. Hence, every allegedly
simple part is at once simple and nonsimple. Consequently, spatial extension
cannot be real. Extension is therefore not a property of the material world
itself; it is a form imposed upon reality by man’s perception.