NATURAL HUMANS TO CULTURAL HUMANS 69
humans, far more than other animals, are dependent upon extragenetic
mechanisms—not merely environmental stimuli, but cultural signals that
partly order and structure behaviour and expectations—because the ge-
netic information humans inherit is far more diffuse than the narrower
and more precisely ordered and effective genetic cues given to cognitively
simpler animals. Cultural norms and expectations, in other words, pro-
vide humans with information without which they could not function.
Evolutionary history in part explains our unique dependence upon cul-
tural knowledge and may well demonstrate the centrality of culture to
the human condition.
67
A variety of philosophers in the eighteenth cen-
tury argued in a more speculative fashion that humans are unlike other
animals in that they rely upon far more than their basic instincts and
partly fashion the world themselves, thus living their lives according to
the conventional worlds of their own making (and remaking). Those who
defended the idea of human sociability as a constitutive element of hu-
manity believed that humans not only can but must live according to
more than their instincts, and the environmental stimuli that trigger them,
in order to function coherently.
Natural humans, humans stripped of their cultural attributes, would
thus be, as Clifford Geertz writes, “unworkable monstrosities with very
few useful instincts, fewer recognizable sentiments, and no intellect: men-
tal basket cases”, far from the placid and well-ordered natural humans
described at length in the Discourse on Inequality.
68
Like many contem-
porary scholars, Geertz mistakenly identifies the reductive concept of a
natural man with what he calls “the Enlightenment view of man”.
69
As I
have argued (and will continue to argue with reference to the anti-impe-
rialist political philosophies of Diderot, Kant, and Herder), there are im-
portant strands of eighteenth-century social and political thought that
take humans to be intrinsically cultural agents who partly transform, and
yet are always situated within, various contexts. Strikingly, anti-imperialist
political theories in the Enlightenment era were almost always informed
by such understandings of humanity.
Rousseau, then, followed the tradition of noble savagery in denying a
crucial and indispensable feature of human nature: cultural agency, an
element moreover that, at certain moments in the Discourse on Inequal-
ity, he appears to deny to a whole set of peoples—the indigenous inhab-
itants of the New World. To be sure, given Rousseau’s theorization of
perfectibility, he too believes that humans, in many respects, make them-
selves. But in his conjectural history, Rousseau does not theorize human
beings from the outset—that is, by their very nature—as social and cul-
tural beings. As we have seen, this has profound consequences for his
interpretation of New World peoples. Rousseau’s need to provide empiri-
cal examples for a supposedly hypothetical category transforms what