DIDEROT AND THE EVILS OF EMPIRE 79
the founders of political authority was partly a response to an artificially
created state of war. “Thus it is”, he writes, again tacitly implicating
Rousseau, “that the first founders of nations are satirized, under the sup-
position of an ideal and chimerical savage state.” (XIX, 2) Diderot chal-
lenges what he views as a fantastical understanding of human nature; as
he bluntly contends, “[m]en were never isolated in the manner here de-
scribed. They carried within them a seed of sociability which tended con-
tinually to be developed.” (XIX, 2) The deep bonds and reciprocal at-
tachments between mothers and children that result from nurturing and
mutual care, the many signs of communication and rudimentary forms of
language, a variety of “natural events” that can “bring together and unite
free and wandering individuals”, and the accidental causes that get hu-
mans to meet and eventually to seek sustenance together all demonstrate
that humans have a “natural tendency to sociability.” (XIX, 2) Both set-
tled and nomadic tribes are examples, in his view, of the mutual associa-
tion that humans form for, at the very least, the purposes of survival.
While for rhetorical effect, Diderot occasionally describes “men without
society” as a foil to the socially complex, oppressive condition of civilized
societies (e.g., XVII, 4), his extensive discussions of New World peoples
and other nonsedentary peoples treat them explicitly as social beings with
consciously created and maintained norms, customs, and collective prac-
tices. In the language that I have been using to summarize such claims,
then, Diderot assumes that humans as such are cultural agents.
The social projects that exemplify the general will of humanity vary
widely, according to Diderot, and represent a range of responses to the
challenge of institutionalizing political rules and practices that foster the
norms of respect and reciprocity. Diderot states repeatedly that different
political institutions should be expected and may well be legitimate given
differences in population, the extent of territory, the impact of a variety of
local opinions, and external influences. For these reasons, it is simply not
the case, he argues, that only the character of rulers can legitimately ac-
count for a plurality of political laws and practices. Perhaps only in the
most absolutist and despotic governments, surmises Diderot, does the
character of the ruler truly wholly shape the polity. Thus, “[t]he science
of government does not contain abstract truths, or rather it does not rest
upon one single principle that extends to all branches of public adminis-
tration.” (XIX, 2) The lack of a predetermined, universal theory of politi-
cal authority and the law makes a detailed knowledge of local circum-
stances a prerequisite for sound and just governance. “The state is a
complicated machine,” he asserts, “which cannot be wound up or set
into motion without a thorough knowledge of all of its components.”
(XIX, 2) As we will see, it follows for Diderot that imperial rule over far-
flung territories is unlikely to yield just political institutions; foreigners