34 CHAPTER TWO
primordial humans’ solitary existence is peaceful because of the bounty of
their environment, their simple (that is, their natural, nonartificial) needs
and desires, and their hard-wired (instinctive, natural) repugnance against
human suffering. Given the method that informs his speculative history, it
becomes clear why New World ethnography, as filtered through the lens
of noble savagery, offered ideal resources for such an account of human
origins. By removing from the distorted figure of ‘civilized man’ the pur-
portedly corrupting layers of science, technology, art, sociability, and even
language, in addition to the psychological states and passions that Rous-
seau contends they breed, the figure that remains is the natural human, a
noble savage thoroughly free of artificiality.
Rousseau emphasizes in the exordium to the Discourse that the “[i]n-
quiries that may be pursued regarding this Subject ought not be taken
for historical truths, but only for hypothetical and conditional reasonings;
better suited to elucidate the Nature of things than to show their genu-
ine origin” (133). Yet, in detailing the precivilized condition of human-
ity, Rousseau makes frequent use of the real-world examples of savages in
order to bolster his assertions about ‘savage man’. The confusion that
results is indicative precisely of the tensions that run through the tradi-
tion of noble savagery, where thinkers would both trumpet the pure and
largely animalistic naturalness of Amerindians while also at times detail-
ing cognitive and institutional features of Amerindian life. In the context
of Rousseau’s developmental account, the related paradoxes arise because
he categorizes New World peoples as part of the middle stage, while also
using them to substantiate a number of his claims about the earlier, pure
state of nature.
The movement from a pure state of nature to the middle stage, in
Rousseau’s conjectural history, involves the development of language, the
transition from an entirely nomadic existence to an occasionally sedentary
life, the origin of a limited amount of private property (largely in the
form of objects that can be carried, rather than of land itself), the for-
mation of family units, and the gradual emergence of nations that are
“united in morals and character, not by Rules or Laws, but by the same
kind of life and of foods, and the influence of a shared Climate.” (169)
Rousseau did not believe that a middle, post-primordial and precivilized,
state was entirely free of corruption and conflict. Once humans become
social creatures, in his view, a corruption of their natural, purely instinc-
tive characteristics inevitably follows. The psychological transformation
wrought by such behavioural and sociological changes is significant be-
cause they give birth to amour propre, or vanity, the vice at the heart of
modern unhappiness and social injustice. Thus, Rousseau notes that vio-
lence is not uncommon among New World peoples, just as it is embed-
ded, though far more pervasively, in European societies. Nevertheless,