302 NOTES TO PAGES 138–140
19. Translation by Allen Wood in Kant, Practical Philosophy, xvii.
20. See Allen W. Wood, general introduction to Kant, Practical Philosophy;
Richard L. Velkley, Freedom and the End of Reason: On the Moral Foundation of
Kant’s Critical Philosophy (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1989), 61–88;
and Beiser, Enlightenment, Revolution, and Romanticism, 32–36. See also Shell,
The Embodiment of Reason, 81–87; and J. B. Schneewind, The Invention of Au-
tonomy: A History of Modern Moral Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1998), 487–92. The classic analysis of Rousseau’s impact on Kant is Ernst
Cassirer, “Kant and Rousseau”, in Rousseau, Kant, Goethe: Two Essays, trans.
James Gutmann, Paul Oskar Kristeller, and John Herman Randall, Jr. (Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 1945), 1–60.
21. In an incisive essay, Christine Korsgaard notes that Kant sometimes uses
‘humanity’ to refer to our personality. But in those cases, she argues, ‘humanity’
simply refers to our perfected ability to set purposes. This implies that the usage of
humanity as personality is simply a perfected variant of the concept of humanity as
cultural agency. My discussion above will show in what sense this is true for Kant,
but this nevertheless elides what I contend are the two clearly distinguishable
concepts of humanity in Kant’s thought. As I argue above, the sense of a digni-
fied humanity in Kant is a distinct conception of humanity that draws upon a
different account of practical reason and freedom than that of cultural agency,
and thus is not simply a version, perfected or otherwise, of our cultural agency.
See Christine M. Korsgaard, “Kant’s Formula of Humanity”, in Creating the
Kingdom of Ends (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 114. See also
Korsgaard, The Sources of Normativity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1996), 122. Cf. Thomas E. Hill, Jr., Dignity and Practical Reason (Ithaca: Cor-
nell University Press, 1992), 38–57; and Mary Gregor, Laws of Freedom (New
York: Barnes & Noble, 1963), 168–69.
22. The further question, of course, is whether the very idea of human dignity,
or the fundamental moral principle (‘the categorical imperative’) that we should
respect the humanity in our persons, can be philosophically justified (that is, ra-
tionally proven, or given a solid foundation). I have not dealt with this question
in this chapter, given that I have focused instead on elucidating Kant’s under-
standing of these claims, reconstructing the social and political concerns that help
give rise to them, and explaining how they inform his attitudes toward culture,
imperialism, and his practical philosophy in general. Although I cannot argue the
point here, my contention along these lines is that the question is not amenable
to rational justification in any way that would avoid either a dogmatic assertion or
a circular argument (the results, in my view, of Kant’s two attempts to offer such
justifications in the Critique of Practical Reason and Groundwork part III respec-
tively). Much of Kant’s approach, however, fits within the critical strictures within
which he attempts to philosophize—his approach does not allow him to (and
thus he does not) support the idea of human dignity with an authoritative appeal
to God (or of some particular religious doctrine or revealed truth), to the funda-
mental organization of the natural world (or its intrinsic ends or purposes), to a
rationally divinable meaning or end of history, or to theoretical reason (to a clear
and distinct intuition of a moral framework or natural laws themselves). All that
remains, for Kant, is (1) our varied experience on the one hand, which he saw as