CONCLUSION 261
dard response to pejorative characterizations of Enlightenment thought
is to affirm its commitment to universal values, and to defend this by
arguing that celebrations of cultural diversity can solidify the traditions
and prejudices that the philosophes rightly attacked. Thus, even the most
perceptive scholars of Enlightenment-era writings who are fully aware of
its diverse sets of arguments and dispositions, and hence the difficulty of
identifying a core Enlightenment project, have responded to critical in-
terpretations by concluding, for instance, that “[t]he moral chaos of the
modern world stems not from the failure of the Enlightenment Project
but from its neglect and abandonment.”
1
The persistent identification of
eighteenth-century thought with the complex set of evolving social, eco-
nomic, and political practices, beliefs, and institutions that are gathered
under the banner of ‘modernity’—and the nearly unanimous agreement
that ‘the Enlightenment’ championed universal values in a manner that
was, rightly or wrongly, at the expense of a number of particular identi-
ties, beliefs, and practice—have either distorted or hidden from view a
number of innovative arguments about cultural difference, humanity, and
imperial politics in the Enlightenment era.
Consider, for instance, one of the most common assertions about En-
lightenment thought: its penchant for universal moral principles. For the
moment, although this understanding involves a wide variety of claims, I
want to signal two key assertions that are especially significant in light of
the issues under study in this book. First, universalism at times refers to
the justification of universal moral judgements to which all human beings
are subject by abstracting from the particularities of social and cultural
life. Second, and closely connected to this, ‘the Enlightenment’ is often
portrayed as universalist because it is said to support the view that there is
such a thing as a universal human nature or ontological essence, which is
fixed, permanent, and readily identifiable, since what are taken to be
ephemeral social and cultural elements can (at least hypothetically) be
stripped away. Bringing these two assertions together, Alasdair MacIntyre
argues that “[i]t was a central aspiration of the Enlightenment.... to
appeal to principles undeniable by any rational person and therefore inde-
pendent of all those social and cultural particularities which the Enlight-
enment thinkers took to be the mere accidental clothing of reason in
particular times and places”.
2
In this view, the most damning feature of
‘the Enlightenment’ consists of its failure to appreciate the plural and
diverse forms of human life.
3
This emphasis on cultural diversity and
moral pluralism, the idea that we must begin to take such particularities
seriously in any cogent moral and political philosophy by viewing them as
integral and meaningful to human life, is often presented, then, as an
indictment of modern thinking or as a repudiation of either modernity as
such or, more specifically, of ‘the Enlightenment project’.
4
In a particularly blunt version of this perspective—one that is nonethe-