of behaviourism to win general acceptance. Nonetheless, the book
remained a classic of analytic philosophy of mind.
However, when Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations appeared posthu-
mously in 1953 it was possible to see ideas that Ryle had displayed vividly
but crudely now presented with far greater subtlety and profundity. It was,
and remains, a matter of controversy how far Ryle, in the development of
his ideas, had drawn on conversations with Wittgenstein and hearsay
accounts of his Cambridge lectures, and how far he had reached similar
conclusions by independent reflect ion.
Wittgenstein left the copyright of his literary remains to three of his
former pupils: Georg Henrik von Wright, Elizabeth Anscombe, and Rush
Rhees. The three philosophers corresponded to different facets of Wittgen-
stein’s own personality and work. Von Wright, who held Wittgenstein’s
Cambridge chair from 1948 to 1951 and then returned to a career in his
native Finland, resembled Wittgenstein the logician of the Tractatus; the
books that first made his reputation were on induction, probability,
and modal logic. Anscombe, an Oxford tutor who in her turn held the
Cambridge chair towards the end of the century, carried forward the work
of the later Wittgenstein on philosophy of mind, and with her book Intention
inaugurated extensive discussion of practical reasoning and the theory of
action. Of the three Rhees was the most sympathetic to the mystical and
fideistic side of Wittgenstein’s temperament, and inspired in Wales a
characteristic school of philosophy of religion.
During the later decades of the twentieth century the literary executors
presided over the publication of Wittgenstein’s extensive Nachlass. Many
volumes appeared, of which the most significant were Philosophical Grammar
(1974) and Philosophical Remarks (1975) from the pre-war manuscripts, and
Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics (1978), Remarks on the Philosophy of
Psychology (1980), plus On Certainty (1969) from later notebooks up until the
time of Wittgenstein’s death. The entire Nachlass was published by Oxford
University Press in 1998, in transcription and facsimile, in an electronic
form prepared by the University of Bergen.
After Wittgenstein’s death many people regarded W. V. O. Quine (1908–
2000) as the doyen of Anglophone philosophy. Having early established a
reputation as a formal logician, Quine spent time with the Vienna Circle,
and in Prague and Warsaw. After his return to the United States in 1936 he
joined the facu lty at Harvard, where he remained for the rest of his
PEIRCE TO STRAWSON
64