‘Function and Concept’, ‘Sense and Reference’, ‘Concept and Object’. Each
of these presented original philosophical ideas of great importance with
astonishing brevity and clarity. They were seen, no doubt, by Frege himself
as ancillary to his concerns with the nature of mathematics, but at the
present time they are regarded as founding classics of modern semantic
theory.4
Between 1884 and 1893 Frege worked on the treatise that should have been
the climax of his intellectual career, the Grundgesetze der Arithmetik, which was
to set out in a complete and formal manner the logicist construction of
arithmetic from logic. The task was to enunciate a set of axioms that would
be recognizably truths of logic, to propound a set of undoubtedly sound
rules of inference, and then from those axioms by those rules to derive, one
by one, the standard truths of arithmetic. The derivation was to occupy
three volumes, of which only two were completed, the first dealing with the
natural numbers, and the second with negative, fractional, irrational, and
complex numbers.
Frege’s ambitious project aborted before it was completed. Between the
publication of the first volume in 1893 and the second in 1903 Frege
received a letter from an English philosopher, Bertrand Russell, pointing
out that the fifth of the initial set of axioms rendered the whole system
inconsistent. This axiom stated, in effect, that if every F is a G, and every G is
an F, then the class of Fs is identical with the class of G s; and vice versa. It
was the axiom which, in Frege’s words, allowed the transition from a
concept to its extension, the transition from concepts to classes that was
essential if it was to be established that numbers were logical objects.
The problem, as Russell pointed out, was that the system, with this
axiom, permits without restriction the formation of classes of classes, and
classes of classes of classes, and so on. Classes must themselves be classifi-
able. Now can a class be a member of itself? Most classes are not (the class of
men is not a man) but some apparently are (e.g. the class of classes is surely
a class). It seems, therefore, that we have two kinds of classes: those that are
members of themselves and those that are not. But the formation of the
class of all classes that are not members of themselves leads to paradox: if it
is a member of itself, then it is not a member of itself, and if it is not a
4 Frege’s contribution to the philosophy of language is detailed in Ch. 5.
PEIRCE TO STRAWSON
42