As examples of language-games Wittgenstein lists obeying and giving orders,
describing the appearance of objects, expressing sensations, giving meas-
urements, constructing an object from a description, reporting an event,
speculating about the future, making up stories, acting plays, guessing
riddles, telling jokes, asking, cursing, greeting, and praying. Each of these
language-games, and many others, need to be examined if we are to
understand language. We can say that the meaning of a word is its use in
a language-game—but this is not a general theory of meaning, it is simply a
reminder that if we wish to give an account of the meaning of a word we
must look for the part it plays in our life. The use of the word ‘game’ is not
meant to suggest that language is something trivial; the word was chosen
because games exhibit the same kind of variety as linguistic activities do.
There is no common feature that marks all games as games, and likewise
there is no one feature that is essential to language—there are only family
likenesses between the countless language-games.
Wittgenstein never abandoned his early view that philosophy is an
activity, not a theory. Philosophy does not discover any new truths, and
philosophical problems are solved not by the acquisition of new informa-
tion, but by the rearrangement of what we already know. The function of
philosophy, Wittgenstein once said, is to untie the knots in our thinking.
This means that the philosopher’s movements will be complicated, but his
result will be as simple as a plain piece of string.
We need philosophy if we are to avoid being entrapped by our language.
Embodied in the surface grammar of our language there is a philosophy
that bewitches us, by disguising from us the variety of ways in which
language functions as a social, interpersonal activity. Philosophical misun-
derstanding will not harm us if we restrict ourselves to everyday tasks,
using words within the language-games that are their primitive homes. But
if we start upon abstract studies—of mathematics, say, or of psychology, or
of theology—then our thinking will be hampered and distorted unless we
can free ourselves of philosophical confusion. Intellectual inquiry will be
corrupted by mythical notions about the nature of numbers, or of the
mind, or of the soul.
Like the positivists, Wittgenstein was hostile to metaphysics. But he
attacked metaphysics not with a blunt instrument like the verification
principle, but by the careful drawing of distinctions that enable him
to disentangle the mixture of truism and nonsense within metaphysical
PEIRCE TO STRAWSON
62