signify, that is to say, what would be specified in a dictionary definition of
them. In logic, connotation is prior to denotation: ‘when mankind fixed the
word wise they were not thinking of Socrates’ (SL 1.2.5.2).
Since ‘name’ covers such a multitude of terms, Mill can accept the
nominalist view that every proposition is a conjunction of names. But this
does not commit him to the Hobbesian view since, unlike Hobbes, he can
appeal to connotation in setting out the truth-conditions of propositions.
A sentence joining two connotative terms, such as ‘all men are mortal’,
tells us that certain attributes (those, say, of animality and rationality) are
always accompanied by the attribute of mortality.
In his second book, Mill discusses infer ence, of which he distinguished
two kinds, real and verbal. Verbal inference brings us no new knowledge
about the world; knowledge of the language alone is sufficient to enable us
to derive the conclusion from the premiss. As an example of a verbal
inference, Mill gives the inference from ‘No great general is a rash man’ to
‘No rash man is a great general’: both premiss and conclusion, he tells us,
say the same thing. There is real inference when we infer to a truth, in the
conclusion, which is not contained in the premisses.
Mill found it very difficult to explain how new truths could be discov-
ered by general reasoning. He accepted that all reasoning was syllogistic,
and he claimed that in every syllogism the conclusion is actually contained
and implied in the premisses. Take the argument from the premisses ‘All
men are mortal, and Socrates is a man’ to the conclusion ‘Socrates is
mortal’. If this syllogism is to be deductively valid, then surely the prop-
osition ‘Socrates is mortal’ must be presupposed in the more general
assumption ‘All men are mortal’. On the other hand if we substitute for
‘Socrates’ the name of someone not yet dead (Mill’s example was ‘the Duke
of Wellington’) then the conclusion does give us new information, but it is
not justified by the evidence summarized in the first premiss. Hence the
syllogism is not a genuine inference:
All inference is from particulars to particulars. General propositions are merely
registers of such inferences already made, and short formulae for making more.
The major premise of a syllogism, consequently, is a formula of this description;
and the conclusion is not an inference drawn from the formula, but an inference
drawn according to the formula; the real logical antecedent or premise being the
particular facts from which the general proposition was collected by induction.
(SL 3.3.4)
LOGIC
98