Plato, in the Philebus, proposed the question whether pleasure or phronesis
constituted the best life. Aristotle’s answer is that properly understood the
two are not in competition with each other as candidates for happiness.
The exercise of the highest form of phronesis is the very same thing as
the truest form of pleasure; each is identical with the other and with
happiness. In Plato’s usage, however, ‘phronesis’ covers the whole range of
intellectual virtue that Aristotle distinguishes into wisdom (phronesis) and
understanding (sophia). If we ask whether happiness is to be identiWed with
the pleasure of wisdom, or with the pleasure of understanding, we get
diVerent answers in Aristotle’s two ethical treatises.
The Nicomachean Ethics identiWes happiness with the pleasurable exercise of
understanding. Happiness, we were told earlier, is the activity of soul in
accordance with virtue, and if there are several virtues, in accordance with
the best and most perfect virtue. We have, in the course of the treatise,
learnt that there are both moral and intellectual virtues, and that the latter
are superior; and among the intellectual virtues, understanding, the scien-
tiWc grasp of eternal truths, is superior to wisdom, which concerns human
aVairs. Supreme happiness, therefore, is activity in accordance with under-
standing, an activity which Aristotle calls ‘contemplation’. We are told that
contemplation is related to philosophy as knowing is to seeking: in some
way, which remains obscure, it consists in the enjoyment of the fruits of
philosophical inquiry (NE 10. 7. 1177a12– b 26).
In the Eudemian Ethics happiness is identiWed not with the exercise of a
single dominant virtue but with the exercise of all the virtues, including
not only understanding but also the moral virtues linked with wisdom (EE
2. 1. 1219a35–9). Activity in accordance with these virtues is pleasant, and so
the truly happy man will also have the most pleasant life ( EE 7. 25.
1249a18–21). For the virtuou s person, the concepts ‘good’ and ‘pleasant’
coincide in their application; if the two do not yet coincide then a person is
not virtuous but incontinent (7. 2. 1237a8–9). The bringing about of this
coincidence is the task of ethics (7. 2. 1237a3).
Though the Eudemian Ethics does not identify happiness with philosophical
contemplation it does, like the Nicomachean Ethics, give it a dominant position
in the life of the happy person. The exercise of the moral virtues, as well as
intellectual ones, is, in the Eudemian Ethics, included as part of happiness; but
the standard for their exercise is set by their relationship to contempla-
tion—which is here deWned in theological rather than philosophical terms.
276
ETHICS