philosophy in the thirteenth century
158
Aquinas explains what he means by making a comparison between sight and
thought. Colours are perceptible by the sense of sight: but in the dark, colours
are only potentially, not actually, perceptible. The sense of vision is only actuated
– a person only sees the colours – when light is present to render them actually
perceptible. Similarly, Aquinas says, the things in the physical world are, in them-
selves, only potentially thinkable or intelligible. An animal with the same senses as
ours perceives and deals with the same material objects as we do; but he cannot
have intellectual thoughts about them – he cannot, for instance, have a scientific
understanding of their nature – for lack of the light cast by the active intellect. We,
because we can abstract ideas from the material conditions of the natural world,
are able not just to perceive, but to think about, and understand, the world.
It is by means of its ideas that the mind understands the world; but this does
not mean that ideas are replicas or pictures of external things from which the
mind reads off their nature. However, because ideas are universal and external
things are particular, it does mean that, for Aquinas, there is no purely intellectual
knowledge of individuals as such. This follows from two Aristotelian theses which
Aquinas accepted: that to understand something is to grasp its form without its
matter; and that matter is the principle of individuation.
If Plato was wrong, as Aquinas thought he was, then there is not, outside the
mind, any such thing as human nature in itself: there is only the human nature of
individual human beings such as Tom, Dick, and Harry. But because the human-
ity of individuals is form embedded in matter, it is not something which can, as
such, be the object of pure intellectual thought. To grasp the humanity of Tom,
the humanity of Dick, and the humanity of Harry we need to call in aid the
senses and the imagination. The humanity of an individual, in Aquinas’ termin-
ology, is ‘thinkable’ (because it is a form), but not ‘actually thinkable’ (because
existing in matter). That is to say, it is, because it is a form, a fit object of the
understanding; but it needs to undergo a metamorphosis if it is to be actually
held in the mind. It is the active intellect which, on the basis of our experience of
individual humans, creates the intellectual object, humanity as such. And human-
ity as such has no existence outside the mind (see Plate 11).
Theorists of the human mind are sometimes grouped into empiricists, rational-
ists, and idealists. Very crudely, empiricists believe that all knowledge of the world
comes from experience; rationalists believe that important knowledge about the
world is inborn; idealists believe that the human mind’s knowledge extends only
to its own ideas. Aquinas’ position differs from each of these, but shares with each
some common ground. Like the empiricists, Aquinas denies that there is innate
knowledge; mind without experience is a tabula rasa, an empty page. But he
agrees with the rationalists against the empiricists that mere experience, of the
kind that humans and animals share, is impotent to write anything on the empty
page. Like the idealists, Aquinas believes that the immediate object of purely
intellectual thought is something which is its own creation, namely, a universal
AIBC08 22/03/2006, 11:02 AM158