Jose Harris
pp. 454–563).
18
Indeed, in Weber’s view, what was commonly deemed
‘irrationality’ was not a deviant or abnormal symptom but an inescapable
feature of human thought and action, and therefore of central concern to
social and political science (Weber 1975,pp.120–32, 191–2, 190–207).
A third problem relates to the implied (and often explicit) suggestion that
irrationality was inherently linked to political extremism and ‘violence’,
whereas rationality was the corollary of liberal constitutionalism and peaceful
legal order. That some political activists of the 1890sand1900s deliberately
linked rejection of reason to their own strategies of violence cannot be
denied, most notably in the cases of Sorel, the Futurists, many anti-Semites,
and some militant suffragettes. Indeed, for Georges Sorel, the cult of the
irrational was no mere strategy but an end in its own right – it was an
intrinsically preferable alternative to what he perceived as the appalling
cultural triumph of rationalistic humanism (Sorel 1916,pp.61–2, 89–92,
101–5). Nevertheless, the suggestion that there was a generic and necessary
link between interest in the ‘irrational’ and resort to political violence, or
between constitutionalism and rejection of violence, seems very much open
to question. Once again the writings of Max Weber, perhaps the greatest
theorist of the power-politics of the fin-de-si
`
ecle epoch, are of relevance here.
Weber focused upon the categorical element of systemic violence inherent
in the inner structures of even the most legitimate, well-ordered and peaceful
states; indeed the very existence of social and political order in Weber’s
view was predicated upon force and violence being exclusively at the state’s
disposal (Weber 1954,pp.338–42). Lenin likewise offers an instr uctive,
though rather different kind of, example. In his 1902 treatise What is to
be Done? Lenin advanced the case for giving absolute priority in politics
to exact science over muddled intuition and pragmatism, to ‘organisation’
rather than ‘spontaneity’, to precise calculation of the relation of means
to ends, and to control of political strategy by a ‘small, compact core’
of highly trained political experts rather than by well-meaning democrats
and blundering amateurs (Lenin 1961–6, v,pp.370–5, 422–5, 430, 433–4,
459–65). This tightly reasoned, indeed ultra-rationalist, approach to politics
was to be the hallmark of Lenin’s lifelong career as a systematic political
theorist (apparent in this earlier period no less than during the October
Revolution of 1917) (Lenin 1961–6, xxvii,pp.323–54, xxxi,pp.17–118).
The success of his analysis in winning away Russian social democratic and
18 More fully set out in Weber’s Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft (1922–5), but central to his thought from a
much earlier period (Weber 2005,pp.454–9).
932