A Logical Theorem 479
Then is al-Farabi simply mistaken? Did Galen reject problematical syl-
logisms but keep his arms round apodictic syllogistic? Well, you may be
attracted by such a view if you are persuaded that Galen’s logical theorem is
the Modal Theorem; but in fact there are pretty good reasons for thinking
that it was not.
First, the Modal Theorem, as I have said, has universal scope: it will
make an apodictic syllogism of any non-apodictic syllogism. Galen’s logical
theorem, on the other hand, is supposed to have a circumscribed domain of
application; for Galen explicitly says that in some cases—and he evidently
means in some cases only—the theorem allows us to move from a possible
conclusion to a necessary conclusion. If the logical theorem is identified as the
Modal Theorem, then we shall have to suppose that Galen somehow came to
convince himself that its scope was restricted to a certain class of syllogism.
Secondly, I said that we might readily suppose the logical theorem to state
something of the form: ‘When such-and-such a syllogism is valid, then so too
is such-and-such another syllogism.’ (The Modal Theorem has that form.) But
although the supposition is readily made, there is no direct warrant for it in
Galen’s text. Galen does not speak of transforming one syllogism into another:
he speaks of showing that the conclusion of a given proof not only holds but
holds of necessity. There is no explicit mention of any second syllogism, and
perhaps there is no need to insert a second syllogism into the text.
Earlier, I argued that when Galen says that ‘some proofs conclude that … it
possibly holds’, we should forget the plain sense of his words and take him
to mean not that some proofs conclude to propositions of the form ‘Possibly
so-and-so’ but rather that some proofs conclude to ‘So-and-so’, where—for
all we yet know—it may be contingently the case that so-and-so. That is to
say, the proof of possibility is simply this:
Gall and safflower attract phlegm.
What attracts phlegm is phlegm-like.
Therefore gall and safflower are phlegm-like.
It is a proof of possibility insofar as, for all that has been thus far argued, the
conclusion of the syllogism may be contingently rather than necessarily true.
Now if that is so, then by the same token, a proof which concludes that ‘of
necessity this holds of that’ ought to conclude not to ‘Necessarily so-and-so’
but rather to ‘So-and-so’, where in fact, as we can show, it is necessary that
so-and-so. In other words, the proof of necessity will be exactly the same as
the proof of possibility, namely: