566 Central limit theorem
This does not mean that ESP does not exist; only that there is no need here to invoke a
paranormal ph enomenon in order to explain what happened.
Solution of exercise 21.7. Let us assume that door A leads to Heaven, and doors B and
C to Hell. If Bayes had chosen A, Saint Peter will open B or C for him; changing hi s mind
means Bayes will go to Hell.
If Bayes had chosen door B, Saint Peter, necessarily, must open door C for him (since he
opens a door leading to Hell), so if Bayes changes his mind, he will go to Heaven. The same is
obviously tru e if Bayes had chosen door C .
Therefore, independently o f his original choic e, if Bayes changes his mind after Saint Peter
has shown him one door, this change of mind will swit ch his destination from the one first
chosen. This means the probability that Bayes will go to Heaven is now 2/3 and the probability
of going to Hell is now 1/3.
Conclusion: well, this rather depends on wh at Bayes really wants — does he want to spend
the rest of his (eternal) life hearing angels play the harp, or is he more interested i n playing
roulette w ith the devils?
Solution of exercise 21.8. This exercise is a simple appli cation of the Bienaymé-Tchebychev
inequality. The goal is that the probability of the grade being too far from m be less than 0.2.
Consider the random variable X
1
+ ···+ X
N
. It has expectation N m, and S
N
has expectation
m. The variance of X
1
+···+X
N
, on the other hand, is equal to N σ
2
, as can be seen by looking
at the centered random variables X
′
i
= X
i
−m, with zero expectation and standard deviation σ.
The variance of the sum X
1
+ X
2
is simply E((X
′1
+ X
′2
)
2
) = E((X
′
1
)
2
) + E((X
′
2
)
2
) = 2σ
2
,
and similarly by induction for the sum of N random variables (since every crossed term has
expectation equal to zero). Hence the standard deviation of X
1
+ ··· + X
N
is
p
N σ and that
of S
N
= (X
1
+ ···+ X
n
)/N i s σ/
p
N.
We are looking for a value of N such that
P
|S
N
−m| ¾
1
2
¶ 0.2.
The Bienaymé-Tchebychev inequality states that we always have
P
|S
N
−m| ¾
ǫσ
p
N
¶ ǫ
2
.
So we need 1/ǫ
2
= 0, 2, or ǫ =
p
5, and it then suffices that
p
5σ
p
N
=
1
2
,
or N = 4 × 5 ×σ
2
= 20 σ
2
to be cert ain that th e desired inequality holds.
For a value σ = 2, one finds N = 80!!! This is rather unrealistic, considering the average
budget of a university. If the graders manage to grade very consistently, so that their individual
standard deviation is σ =
1
2
, it will be enough to take N = 5. This is still a l ot but will
provoke fewer cardiac incidents among university administrators.
However, notice that those estimates are not optimal, because the Bienaymé-Tchebychev in-
equality can be refined sig nificantly if the distribution o f the random variables X
i
is known (it
is only in itself a worst-case scenario). We know that 80 graders will achieve the desired g o al ,
independently of the distribution (given the expectation and standard deviation), but it is very
likely that a smaller number suffices.
Solution of exercise 21.9. The probability densities of the masses of the first and second
egg, respectively, are
f
1
(x) =
0 i f x /∈ [50, 60] ,
1
10
if x ∈ [50, 60] ,
and f
2
(x) =
0 if x /∈ [40, 45] ,
1
5
if x ∈ [40, 45] .