CAUSATION
— 95—
question is neatly exemplified by two contempo-
rary schools of thought on causation, one repre-
sented by Wesley Salmon (1925–2001), the other
highlighted by the philosophy of Philip Kitcher
(1947– ). Salmon has argued that there does exist,
after all, an empirically verifiable physical connec-
tion between cause and effect. It is to be found in
the notion of a causal process, rather than in that
of a causal interaction, which Hume mistakenly
took as his paradigm. Furthermore, thanks to the
theory of relativity that sets an upper limit to the
transmission of causal signals, we can now empir-
ically distinguish between genuinely causal
processes (e.g., light rays traveling at straight lines
from a rotating beacon to the surrounding wall of,
say, the Colosseum) and mere pseudoprocesses
(e.g., a spot of light “traveling” along the inner
wall of the Colosseum as a result of a central bea-
con rotating at very high speed). While pseudo-
processes may travel at arbitrarily high velocities,
they cannot transmit information as only causal
processes can. Similarly, the actions of a cowboy
on a cinema screen are pseudoprocesses. When,
in excessive excitement, you shoot him, it has no
lasting effect on the cowboy, but only on the
screen. Thus, in Salmon’s view, the capacity to
transmit information (or rather, conserved energy)
constitutes empirical proof that the relevant proc-
ess is genuinely causal in nature rather than a
mere pseudoprocess.
According to this realist view, therefore, cau-
sation is a robust physical ingredient within our
world itself, entailing necessary and sufficient
conditions (or causal laws, probabilistic or other-
wise), rather than being entailed by these. Causa-
tion is essentially a “local” affair, depending on
the intrinsic features of two causally related
events. By contrast, causal laws and necessary and
sufficient conditions are “global” features, de-
pending on the world as a whole. Consequently,
on this realist view, causality may be entirely com-
patible with indeterminism, while theories
couched in terms of necessary and sufficient con-
ditions run into grave difficulties when confronted
with the pervasiveness of indeterminacy in the
subatomic realm.
Yet Salmon’s theory has not been without its
detractors. Thus, having confronted the theory
with ingenious counter examples, Kitcher has ar-
gued that Salmon’s theory, just like the empiricist
theories before him, ultimately comes to rest on
the truth of empirically unverifiable counterfactu-
als. By contrast, Kitcher’s own theory places
causality squarely within a Kantian-Peircian per-
spective. Immanuel Kant (1724–1804), while con-
ceding to Hume that causality may be unobserv-
able in the physical world, contradicted Hume’s
conclusion that therefore causality is not a real fea-
ture of the world as we know it. Indeed, causality
may not be a feature positively discoverable in
what Kant called the noumenal world, that is, the
world as it exists in itself, without regard to the
structural limitations of human knowledge. But
then again, nothing is so discoverable or attributa-
ble. And yet causality is a property objectively as-
cribable to the phenomenal world, that is, the
world as structured by the conceptual and percep-
tual features inherent in human cognitive capaci-
ties. As a result of the necessarily synthetic activi-
ties of human reason, one cannot conceive of the
empirical world except in terms of causes and ef-
fects. The causal relation is therefore as firmly and
objectively established as are space and time,
which constitute the a priori forms of perception of
the empirical world. These are all verifiable attrib-
utes of the physical world, which is part of the
phenomenal world, the only kind of world hu-
mans are capable of knowing in principle.
Thus, the fundamental notion of causation re-
ceives a distinctly epistemological underpinning in
Kantian philosophy. This is what ties Kitcher’s phi-
losophy of causation in part to the Kantian tradi-
tion. Thus, Kitcher has stated that the because of
causation derives from the because of explanation.
Rather than being an independent metaphysical
notion, what may and may not be recognized as
truly causal relations depends in the final analysis
on epistemological constraints. In Kitcher’s view
the ultimate aim of science is to generate theories
of the universe as unified and simple (or all-en-
compassing) as possible. Which theories are finally
recognized—in the ideal end of inquiry, to borrow
the famous words of the pragmatist Charles
Sanders Peirce (1839–1914)—as optimally unified
and robust thus determine what causes are recog-
nized as genuinely operative and effective in the
only world humans can possibly come to under-
stand. Thus, in Kitcher’s view, the metaphysical
significance of causation ultimately derives from its
key role in the best possible theory of the universe
we will be able to generate. In a sense, therefore,