Hegel’s Idealism 49
a challenging account of how Hegel’s system works in general, particularly how
the Phenomenology relates to the Logic.
Nonetheless, Pippin’s reading remains controversial with Hegel scholars, where
Ameriks and others have questioned its textual accuracy, and how far it does
justice to Hegel’s actual position and procedures. It is not possible to go into all
the details here, but one issue is fundamental, namely whether Pippin is right to
claim that Hegel followed Kant in attempting to deduce the categories from the
conditions of self-consciousness, to ‘ ‘‘ground’’ them in the ‘‘I’’ ’.¹⁶ For Pippin, as
we have seen, such ‘grounding’ is essential to the critical turn in metaphysics, as
no other basis for metaphysics as the non-empirical inquiry into ‘how the world
must be’ can be taken seriously after Kant. Nonetheless, as Pippin recognizes,
in presenting his account of the categories in the Logic, Hegel seems to go
further than this, in framing his argument in more straightforwardly ontological
terms, and so ‘slips frequently from a ‘‘logical’’ to a material mode, going far
beyond a claim about thought or thinkability, and making a direct claim about
the necessary nature of things, direct in the sense that no reference is made to
a ‘‘deduced’’ relation between thought and thing’.¹⁷ Now, Pippin argues that
these ‘slips’ are merely apparent.¹⁸ However, critics of Pippin’s approach are
constitutes the nature of the Notion is recognized as the original synthetic unity of apperception,as
unity of the Ithink, or of self-consciousness’ (Hegel, SL, 584 [Werke, VI: 254]). However, Pinkard
has argued that comments such as these should not be taken to imply that Hegel is taking the
transcendental turn, but rather that he is drawing attention to the way in which the structure of the
Notion resembles the structure of the unity of apperception, so that it is the structural similarity
between the Notion and the ‘I think’ that is here being highlighted: ‘Thus, in Hegel’s eyes, what
is important in the Kantian philosophy is not its attempt to derive everything from the conditions
of self-consciousness, but its attempt to construct a self-subsuming, self-reflexive explanation of
the categories. Self-consciousness is only an instance of such a reflexive structure’ (Pinkard, ‘The
Categorial Satisfaction of Self-Reflexive Reason’, 8). Cf. Hegel, SL, 583 [Werke, VI: 253], where
Hegel says that ‘the I is the pure Notion itself which, as Notion, has come into existence’because
the I is like the Notion, in combining the moments of universality and individuality, and thus of
being a unity that contains difference within it: ‘This absolute universality whichisalsoimmediately
an absolute individualization, and an absolutely determined being, which is a pure positedness and
is this absolutely determined being only through its unity with the positedness, this constitutes the
nature of the I as well as the Notion; neither the one nor the other [i.e. the I and the Notion]
can be truly comprehended unless the two indicated moments [of universality and individuality]
are grasped at the same time both in their abstraction and also in their perfect unity’. Henrich
explains what Hegel is getting at here as follows: ‘By saying ‘‘I think,’’ the self asserts its distinctive
existence; but the self also knows, with respect to the structure of this act, that it does not differ
from other selves ....For reasons that now may well be evident, Hegel says that the ontological
constitution of the self is the structure of the Notion’ (Dieter Henrich, Between Kant and Hegel:
Lectures on German Idealism, ed. David S. Pacini (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press,
2003), 323).
¹⁶ Pippin, Hegel’s Idealism, 33. ¹⁷ Ibid., 187.
¹⁸ See, for example, ibid., 193: ‘Thus, if there is a logical problem in Hegel’s introduction of
finitude, it does not lie in carelessly confusing the conceptual with the real order. I have tried to
show that the issues are conceptual throughout and determined by the overall conceptual strategy
of the Logic’.